RESEARCH METHODOLOGY
Block 1: Basics of Research in Philosophy
UNIT 1 INTRODUCTION
TO RESEARCH IN GENERAL
1.1 INTRODUCTION
M S Sridhar understands research as “systematic,
controlled, empirical, critical and self-correcting investigation of
hypothetical propositions about the presumed relations among natural
phenomena,”: i.e., Systematic & controlled empirical self-correcting research
is a combination of both experience & reasoning and must be regarded as the
most successful approach to the discovery of truth (particularly in natural
sciences). Since it involves experience and critical reasoning, it may be
regarded as the “most successful approach” to the discovery of truth. Further,
we can claim that in a general way, everyone does research, but they do not
write it down. Without trustworthy and tested published research available we
are dangerously lost in the experience, opinions and hearsay and such a data
cannot be used for further study.
In short research methodology may be defined as the
“science of studying how research is done scientifically (Sridhar).” It is a
way to systematically solve the research problem by logically adopting various
steps. Proper methodology, employed in research, helps to understand not only
the products of scientific inquiry but the process itself. Such a research
methodology aims to describe and analyze methods, throw light on their
limitations and resources, clarify their presuppositions and consequences,
relating their potentialities to the twilight zone at the ‘frontiers of
knowledge.’ Thus research methodology provides the tools for conducting serious
and useful research. It is applicable to all fields of science, including
humanities and philosophy. In this unit we study further about research in
general, the tools used for it and the methods employed for doing research. In
the concluding part, we focus on the outcome of the research in terms of report
or paper, which further advances the useful human knowledge.
1.2 RESEARCH
IN GENERAL
It may be proper to begin by saying what research is
not. Definitely it is not mere information gathering. It is not even mere
shifting of facts from one source to another. Further it is not merely
rummaging for information, which cannot be properly made use of. Positively
stated, research is the systematic process of collecting and analysed
information to increase our understanding of the phenomenon under study. It is
the function of the researcher to contribute to the understanding of the
phenomenon and to communicate that understanding to others (Venkataram 2010).
Research is thus about understanding an issue or
asking and answering a complex question or solving a problem. So, to start
with, we need to identify an issue, question, or problem. Then we need to
discuss with people who want or need your study. Listening to their suggestions
and problems will help us. Further, we need to find out what's already known
about it. For this talk with experts and/or read their reviews and the other
original research on the topic by different scholars. Then we need to plan,
budget and proceed with our study accordingly. Do not exceed the time limit and
the budget of our planned study. Then we need to conduct research, record our
findings in writing and submit it for assessment. Publication in quality
journals enhances the worth of the study and makes it available to larger
audience. In academic circles the slogan “publish or perish” still dominates.
It helps to have a good supervisor, good colleagues,
and/or knowledge or practical experience of and affinity for a topic (See
Hopkins 2010). It is essential to read journal articles to find out what's
already known. Many authors also often point out topics for future research.
This prevents doing research on an area already explored and thus prevents
wasting valuable time and effort. It may be emphasized that most serious
research projects are supposed to be original investigations. Either you obtain
new data or information about a phenomenon. Or you reach a novel conclusion and
try to publish it. Briefly we can say that the distinct characteristics of
research is that it originates with a concrete question; requires clear articulation
of a goal and a specific plan for proceeding. Usually research divides a
principal problem into more manageable sub-problems.
Benefits of Research Methodology
Sridhar (2010) formulates the following benefits of
adequate research methodology both for the researcher and for the body of
useful knowledge.
1. Advancement of wealth of human knowledge in any
field.
2. Provides tools of research to look at life
objectively.
3. Develops a critical and scientific attitude,
disciplined thinking or a bent of mind to observe objectively (scientific
deduction & inductive thinking); Skills of research will pay-off in long
term particularly in the µage of information (or too often of misinformation)
4. Enriches investigator and their practices; it provides opportunity to study a
subject in depth; Enable us to make intelligent decisions; Understand the
problem which no other kind of work can match
5. As consumers, research output helps to inculcate
the ability to evaluate and use results of earlier research with reasonable
confidence and take rational decisions
6. Doing research is the best way to learn to read
and think critically and creatively.
Check Your Progress I
1.3 RESEARCH
CIRCLE
Research is guided by the specific research problem,
question or hypothesis. It accepts certain critical assumptions. It definitely
requires the collection and interpretation of data in an attempt to resolve the
problem that initiated the research. This leads to further clarification of the
question and the proposed solutions. Thus research is, by its nature, cyclical
or, more exactly, spiral or helical. Research originates with a question:
Examples: Are philosophers accepted well in the society? What do street
children eat in a day? Why do poor people appear happier? What is the
relationship between belief in God and good moral life? It requires clear articulation of a goal:
What problem do you want to solve? Moral degradation? Deepening of faith in
God? Change of behaviour? Praying more
often? Building up an adequate world-view?
Further, good research requires a specific plan. It is not groping
in the dark to find a solution. In fact, it is a planned discovery with
outlined steps for tacking the problem. It implies a design of study specific
to get relevant data needed. In a good research we need to divide problem into
sub-problems. The main problem is divided to into more manageable problems that
will answer the main problem. (“Manage the unavoidable and avoid the
manageable”). Example: Main problem: “How do you go from Pune to Delhi?”
Sub-problems: What are the ways to go there? What is the most convenient
transportation? How much will it cost to travel by these routes? How long will
the trip last? This, in turn, is guided by specific research problems,
questions and hypothesis. A hypothesis is a logical supposition, a reasonable
guess, an educated conjecture that provides a tentative explanation for the
phenomenon under investigation. It can also provide information in resolving
the specific problem and in the process, the main research problem. Ex. If you
switch on the lamp and it does light what is your reasonable guess as to the
reason why it does not light?
A good research accepts certain critical
assumptions. Assumptions are similar to axioms in geometry – self –evident
truths -the sine non qua of research. They must be valid for the research to be
meaningful. For example, if a research wants to evaluate the knowledge gained
from a nutrition education class, one assumption would be regular attendance to
the class of participants. A good research requires collection and
interpretation of data to resolve problem initiated. Data collected based on
objectives or research questions. Data collected becomes meaningful when it is
interpreted correctly. Methodology of the project controls how data are to
be collected, arranged, synthesized and
interpreted. A good research by nature is cyclical, or
spiral or helical. It follows
logical developmental steps as follows: Questioning mind asks “why?” One
question becomes the problem. Later, problem divided into simpler sub-problems.
Then preliminary data gathered. It may be that data point to alternative
solution. So further data collected more systematically. Then the data are
processed, leading to the possible discovery. This will enable the researcher
to see if the hypothesis supported or not. If the hypothesis is proved wrong,
modifications are made to it and the process repeats itself, till a satisfactory
hypothesis is formulated. Thus good research process.
Remark on the credibility of materials used in
research: It is important for us to know the reliability of the materials that
we base the data or information used in our research. Every materials we get
should not be used, since they may be prejudiced or motivated. Some significant
questions to find out the reliability of the already existing research material
are: In what source did you find the article? Was it reviewed by experts in the
field before publication? Does the article have a stated research question or
problem? Or, can you determine the focus
of the work? Does the article describe the collection of data, or does it
synthesize other studies in which data
were collected? Is the article logically organized and easy to follow? Does the article contain that outlines and
reviews previous studies? In what way is this relevant to the research problem?
Are the procedures clear enough that you could repeat the work and get similar
results? How were the data collected and how were they analyzed? Do you agree
with what was done? Do you agree with
the interpretation of results? Reflect on the entire article. What, for you is
most important? What are interesting? What are the strengths and weaknesses?
Will you remember the article in the future?
1.4 TOOLS
OF RESEARCH
A tool is a specific mechanism or strategy that
researchers use to collect, manipulate or interpret data. Not to equate tools
of research with methodology. A methodology is the general approach that a
researcher takes in carrying out the
research process. Six general tools of research are: Library and its resources
(most useful for philosophy students), Computer and software, Techniques of measurement,
Statistics (The program SPSS is
recommended for research based on statistics), The human mind (this is the
strength of philosophy students), Language.
The library
For a philosophical research the library is always
the starting point. Here the following will be very beneficial: Referring to
the Card catalogue, Browsing through Indexes and abstracts, Consulting the
Reference librarian, if s/he is accessible. Browsing the shelves gives a first
hand knowledge of the books and journals available on the topic of research.
Computer and Software
In today’s context, good research cannot be done
without adequate computer facilities. Computer facilitates not just writing,
but collecting data (internet, online journals, libraries, etc.) and processing
them. Some software packages for qualitative searches are NVivo, Q-Method,
WEFT. For quantitative research, some of the softwares used are: Excel, XLSTAT,
SAS and SPSS. So for any research today adequate and appropriate use of
internet and computer is a necessary.
Techniques of Measurement
Measurement may be done in the laboratory or in the
world outside. Interviews serve a useful function. Measurement is limiting the
data of any phenomenon- substantial or insubstantial – so that those data may
be interpreted and compared to
acceptable qualitative or quantitative standard. So the techniques used in
measurement are of vital importance for the result we arrive at. Validity and
reliability of measurement instrument is to be tested. Validity – extent to
which the instrument measures what it is supposed to measure. Reliability – the
consistency with which a measuring instrument yields a certain result when the
entity being measured has not changed. Both validity and reliability reflect
the degree to which we may have error in measurements.
Statistics
In order to process the result from data
collected, statistical processing &
analysis are to be done, especially in cases of large sample. Statistical
methods are helpful to test the accuracy of the results obtained. Today we can
better do it using statistical softwares. So a basic knowledge of statistics is
necessary for any researcher.
The human mind
Truly, the strategies used by the human mind to
discover the unknown helps us in testing the hypothesis, which could become the
answer to the question to be answered. Deductive logic: Reasoning that begins
with a premise (assumptions, widely accepted “truths” then to the conclusion;
useful for generating hypothesis and testing theories. Critical thinking: Involves evaluating information or argument
in terms of accuracy and worth; it may involve: Inductive reasoning: It begins
with an observation from where conclusions are drawn ; observe sample and draw
generalization to the population. Scientific method: Method where insight into
the unknown is made by 1) identifying a problem that defines the goal , 2) states
the hypothesis that when confirmed, resolves the problem , 3) gathering data
relevant to the hypothesis, 4) analyzing and interpreting data to see if data
supported the hypothesis nor not; also uses both deductive and inductive
reasoning.
Language for adequate expression
Proper use of language enables us not only to
communicate but also to think more effectively. Clear and concise use of
language in writing is important in research. Writing down ideas helps the
investigator to get clarity of mind. This, in turn, is useful to organizes
thoughts systematically to give the proposed answer to the readers. Writing
down the answer is helpful in detecting
gaps and logical flaws in thinking in formulating the final answer.
1.5 METHODS:
QUANTITATIVE OR QUALITATIVE
The method used in research may be quantitative or
qualitative. Qualitative methods are
often required. It may be remembered that often you arrive at an answer by
applying logic (= common sense?) and skepticism to your knowledge and to the
information you gather. So let us be wary of conventional wisdom and your own
prejudices.
Quantitative method in Research that with the
quantities of things and that involves the measurement of quantity or amount.
With quantitative method we gather data with an instrument, such as a
stopwatch, a blood test, a video analysis package, or a structured
questionnaire. Here we derive measures or variables from the data, then
investigate relationships among the variables. Here testing of a hypotheses
becomes easy. The error of measurement are crucial since we know that almost
all measures have possibility of errors. Such errors affect the relationship
between measure, leading to errors in validity and reliability of the final
result. So a pilot study to investigate
error can be carried out first.
Qualitative research deals with the quality, type,
or components of a group. It is usually exploratory in nature and uses
procedures such as in-depth interviews and focus group interviews to gain
insights and propose solutions to problems
posed by the investigator. With qualitative methods we gather information or
themes from texts, conversations or loosely structured interviews, then we try
to articulate a coherent story. The open-ended nature of these methods allows
for more flexibility and serendipity in identifying factors and practical
strategies than the formal structured quantitative approach. It is possible
that in qualitative research, the direction of the research may change
mid-stream. Software such as NVivo, Q-Method or WEFT can be of help in
qualitative analysis.
Other formal procedures that enhance trustworthiness
of the result are: Triangulation – Triple checking of a hypothesis that aims
for congruence of information from
various sources. respondent validation: Here the respondent is asked check the
researcher’s hypothesis in a scale of strongly agree to strongly disagree. Peer
debriefing: colleagues of the investigator or or experts can be asked to check
the analysis. Hybrid or mixed method: Here we may analyze a sample of cases
first qualitatively. Then we may code
information into values of variables to make inferences about a population
quantitatively.
Qualitative methods applied to a sample often result
in a small sample size because (1) subjects are hard to get, the interviews are
too time consuming, or (2) the researchers dislike the idea of large samples.
But a study with a small sample can adequately characterize only strong
associations (large effects) in a population. So, these small-scale qualitative
studies are not definitive for a small or trivial effect, which may be actually
important in the hypothesis formulated. Furthermore, open-ended inquiry is
equivalent to assaying many variables, so there is a high risk of finding a
spurious association. It may be emphasized that if the sample is small, the
spurious association will be strong. Therefore, small-scale qualitative studies
are not definitive even for a moderate or large effect. So based on our reasonable guess from qualitative
methods, we may use quantitative methods or surveys to reinforce our answers.
Such a combined method is more useful.
The conclusion is: when using qualitative methods to generalize to a
population, you need a large sample to characterize small effects. So a hybrid
of qualitative and quantitative may be more profitable for some research.
Concluding Remarks
Qualitative research methods have been developed and
refined through attempts to understand the patterns and associations in human
behaviour and relationships in disciplines such as sociology, anthropology and
educational psychology. However, they also formed the basis of the natural
sciences where the natural world was initially described and chronicled by
narrative researchers. Qualitative and quantitative methods are not mutually exclusive,
rather, different degrees of mixing of the methods occur as the following
examples illustrate. Both qualitative and quantitative research is
fundamentally concerned with discerning similarities and differences in what
they choose to observe. New insights and models are suggested by the nature of
these contrasts and approximations, whether they are measured in numbers or
described in words. However, each mode of research, each way of looking at the
world, creates different modes of knowing and understanding.
Adding qualitative research methods to the
quantitative methods used in general practice research will allow the
development of a research base for the discipline that matches its practice and
its values, and opens up new questions to research. Qualitative research often
demands an examination of the assumptions behind a research question and the
influences on our thinking. This process increases our understanding of the
forces shaping all our research including personal experience, political constraints
and academic acceptability. This can clarify the limitations of research as
well as leading to further research questions. (Griffiths and Marinker 1996)
1.6 THE
PRODUCT: RESEARCH REPORT OR PAPERS
A major goal of research is prepare several research
papers based upon the studies undertaken. Written and oral communications
skills are probably the most universal qualities sought in a good research.
General form of a research paper
An objective of organizing a research paper is to
allow people to read your work selectively. When I research a topic, I may be
interested in just the methods, a specific result, the interpretation, or
perhaps I just want to see a summary of the paper to determine if it is
relevant to my study. To this end, many journals require the following
sections, submitted in the order listed, each section to start on a new page.
There are variations of course. Some journals call for a combined results and
discussion, for example, or include materials and methods after the body of the
paper. The well known journal Science does away with separate sections
altogether, except for the abstract. (Caprette) Your papers are to adhere to
the form and style required for the Journal of Biological Chemistry,
requirements that are shared by many journals in the life sciences. These
general guidelines are to be followed in any written reports, except when the
guides or editors give explicitly different instructions.
• To
make a paper readable
• Print
or type using a 12 point standard font, such as Times, Geneva, Bookman,
Helvetica, etc.
• Text
should be double spaced on 8 1/2" x 11" paper with 1 inch margins,
single sided
• Number
pages consecutively
• Start
each new section on a new page
• Adhere
to recommended page limits, set by the guide.
• Mistakes
to avoid
• Placing
a heading at the bottom of a page with the following text on the next page
(insert a page break!)
• Dividing
a table or figure - confine each figure/table to a single page
• Submitting
a paper with pages out of order
• In
all sections of your paper
• Use
normal prose including articles ("a", "the," etc.)
• Stay
focused on the research topic of the paper
• Use
paragraphs to separate each important point (except for the abstract)
• Indent
the first line of each paragraph
• Present
your points in logical order
• Use
present tense to report well accepted facts - for example, 'the sky is blue.’
• Use
past tense to describe specific results - for example, “In 1783 Kant wrote the
Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics to
summarise his main views.”
• Avoid
informal wording, don't address the reader directly, and don't use jargon,
slang terms, or superlatives
• Avoid
use of superfluous pictures - include only those figures necessary to
presenting results
In any written report or paper the following
divisions are to be made scrupulously.
Title Page: Select an informative title as
illustrated in the examples in your writing portfolio example package. Include
the Full name(s) and address(es) of all authors, the name(s) of guide(s) and date submitted.
Abstract: The summary should be two hundred words or
less. And normally it should be limited to one paragraph. The purpose of
abstract is to introduce the main findings of the report very briefly to an
interested reader.
Introduction: The purpose of an introduction is to
acquaint the reader with the rationale behind the work, with the intention of
defending it. It places the work in a
theoretical context, and enables the reader to understand and appreciate your
objectives.
Materials and Methods: There is no specific page
limit, but a key concept is to keep this section as concise as you possibly
can. People will want to read this material selectively. The reader may only be
interested in one formula or part of a procedure. Materials and methods may be
reported under separate subheadings. The objective of this section is to
document all specialized materials and general procedures, so that another
individual may use some or all of the methods in another study or judge the
scientific merit of the work. It is not to be a step by step description of
everything the investigator did, nor is a methods section a set of
instructions.
Results: The page length of this section is set by
the amount and types of data to be reported. Continue to be concise, using
figures and tables, if appropriate, to present results most effectively. See
recommendations for content, below. The purpose of a results section is to
present and illustrate the findings. Make this section a completely objective
report of the results, and save all interpretation for the discussion.
Discussion: The objective in this section is to
provide an interpretation of the results and support for all of the
conclusions, using evidence from the experiment and generally accepted
knowledge, if appropriate. The significance of findings should be clearly
described. Interpret the data in the discussion in appropriate depth. This
means that when we explain a phenomenon we must describe mechanisms that may
account for the observation. If the results differ from the original
expectations, explain why that may have happened. If the results agree, then
describe the theory that the evidence supported. It is never appropriate to
simply state that the data agreed with expectations. We need to elaborate.
Decide if each hypothesis is supported, rejected, or if we cannot make a
decision with confidence. Do not simply dismiss a study or part of a study as
"inconclusive." Normally, an inconclusive study is not really a
scientific study.
Bibliography or Literature Cited: List all
literature cited in the paper, in alphabetical order, by first author. In a
proper research paper, only primary literature is used (original research
articles authored by the original investigators). Be cautious about using web
sites as references - anyone can put just about anything on a web site, and we
have no sure way of knowing if it is truth or fiction. If we are citing an on
line journal, use the journal citation (name, volume, year, page numbers).
Sometimes some of the papers may not require references, and if that is the
case simply state that "no references were consulted."
Writing to communicate: Say what we mean to say
clearly and consciously. Keep primary objective in writing and focus discussion
accordingly. Provide overview of what will be discussed. Organize ideas from
general to specific using headings and subheadings. Provide transitional phrase,
sentences or paragraphs to help readers follow the flow of thought. Use
concrete examples to make abstract ideas understandable. Use appropriate
punctuation. Use tables and figures to present findings more adequately.
Summarize what was said at the conclusion of the paper. Anticipate revision of
draft of report.
1.7
LET US SUM UP
In this unit we have seen the importance of research
and research methodology in fostering knowledge. We dealt with the process of
research and the tools of research. Then we saw how as a scientific technique,
research methodology leads to scientifically verifiable results helping us to
solve problems efficiently.
1.8
KEY WORDS
Triangulation: It is a triple checking of a
hypothesis that aims for congruence of information from various sources.
Qualitative Method: Methods of social research that
do not depend on comparing quantities. It involve the collection and analysis
of information based on its quality and NOT quantity. They are methods in which
the results are primarily conveyed in visual or verbal forms.
UNIT 2 ORIGINAL UNITY OF PHILOSOPHY AND SCIENCE
Contents
2.0 Objectives
2.1 Introduction
2.2 Myth, Philosophy and Science: Original
Unity
2.3 The Myth: A Spiritual Metaphor
2.4 Myth, Philosophy and Science
2.5 The Greek Quest for Unity
2.6 The Ionian School
2.7 Towards a Grand Unification Theory or
Theory of Everything
2.8 Einstein’s Perennial Quest for Unity
2.9 Conclusion:
Philosophical Quest
2.10 Let us
Sum up
2.11 Key
Words
2.12 Further
Readings and References
2.0 OBJECTIVES
• To
study basic human quest for unity that has given rise to philosophy, religion
and science.
• To
trace the origin of human knowledge to our quest for understanding: the self,
world and God.
2.1 INTRODUCTION
In order to trace the original human quest meaning
through philosophy and science, we first speak of humans as the myth-making
animals. Once we understand myth in a positive sense, then we can make use of
our philosophical and scientific quest as emerging from our innermost sense of
unity. For this purpose we use insights from the beginnings of philosophy, the
Ionians who searched for the ultimate that is the basis of everything else.
Then we look into the greatest scientist, ever lived, Albert Einstein, who
painstakingly tried to formulate a unified theory of everything. Our argument
is that there is an human quest for unity, out of which philosophy and science
have emerged. So there was that original unity. Now though they follow
different methods and have different goals, at the ultimate level, as human
beings we use everything at our disposal – science, religion and philosophy –
to open ourselves to that unity. Such a search for the original unity, in fact
promotes diversity and thus makes our lives
really human.
2.2 MYTH,
PHILOSOPHY AND SCIENCE: ORIGINAL UNITY
As we know, humans are part of large and complex
cosmic tradition going back to about 13.7 billion years, when the Big Bang gave
rise to the known universe of today! About 4.5 billion years ago the solar
system was formed. Further, 4.5 million years ago humans (Homo sapiens)
evolved. About 20,000 years ago Neanderthals would sit around the fire at night
watching starry sky and listening to the sounds from far. They were trying to
understand the world around them. They were trying to make sense of life, but
more importantly, of death. How did dead people show up in their sleep, in
their dreams? What could be made of their own impending deaths? In order to
honor the dead person, Neanderthals buried their dead with flowers and beads.
They also took care of the sick and elderly. In trying to understand death
through ritual and ceremony, Neanderthals gave us their greatest gift:
mythology. This endures till today though in different forms (Pandikattu 2009)
At first primitive humans thought very little about
anything but immediate things. They were preoccupied thinking such things as:
“Here is a bear; what shall I do?” Or “There is a squirrel; how can I get it?”
Until language had developed to some extent there could have been little
thinking beyond the range of actual experience, for language is the instrument
of thought as bookkeeping is the instrument of business. It records and fixes
and enables thought to get on to more and more complex ideas. Primordial man, before he could talk,
probably saw very vividly, mimicked very cleverly, gestured, laughed, danced,
and lived, without much speculation about whence he came or why he lived. He
feared the dark, no doubt, and thunderstorms and big animals and queer things
and whatever he dreamt about, and no doubt he did things to propitiate what he
feared or to change his luck and please the imaginary powers in rock and beast
and river. He made no clear distinction between animate and inanimate things;
if a stick hurt him, he kicked it; if the river foamed and flooded, he thought
it was hostile. His thought was probably very much at the level of a bright
little contemporary boy of four or five. But since he had little or no speech
he would do little to pass on the fancies fantasies that came to him, and
develop any tradition or concerted acts about them.
In these questions of primitive thought, we must
remember that the so called “lowly and savage” peoples of today probably throw
very little light on the mental state of men before the days of fully developed
language. Primordial man could have had little or no tradition before the
development of speech. All primitive
peoples of today, on the contrary, are soaked in tradition - the tradition of
thousands of generations. They may have weapons like their remote ancestors and
methods like them, but what were slight and shallow impressions on the minds of
their predecessors are now deep and intricate grooves worn throughout the
intervening centuries generation by generation. Thus the language enabled them
to create myths and thus perceive meaning in their own lives.
The word “mythos” is related to the Greek meaning
“to be spoken with the mouth”. All myths are fundamentally, if not
historically, true and lead to the highest of truths. The myths and their many
facets have given birth to religion, mysticism, spirituality, philosophy or in
short, to the different articulations of human quest for meaning. Myth is
humankind’s basic method of communicating our meaning of the cosmos and
answering the why and how regarding birth, life, death of humans and the
rhythms of nature. Mythology lives and breathes in us. In other words, we live
and breathe our myths. Myth constitutes our very existence. We have been
imprinted with certain fears and faiths that have dwelt in our collective
unconscious for thousands of years. Mythology is the language of the universe
of rituals, ceremonies and symbols. They are the enactments of our desire to
have mystical experience, communion with reality. With and through myths we
bathe ourselves in the Mystery.
2.3 THE
MYTH: A SPIRITUAL METAPHOR
The crucial fact about mythology is that it is a
spiritual metaphor. Myth is a guidepost to a higher truth or understanding,
which if taken literally destroys its original function and meaning. For
example, the myth of Adam and Eve, is a myth describing how humans became
conscious and further, conscious of evil. The story is that Eve convinced Adam
to eat the apple and we were thrown out of paradise. A literal interpretation
of this myth has led generations of people to believe women to be the cause for
evil in humanity and think of their suffering in childbirth as a just
punishment. By analyzing this myth exegetically and interpreting it, we learn
that the serpent in the story in all cultures, with the exception of the Old
Testament, represents wisdom, the feminine goddess, power and rebirth because
it sheds its skin. The tree is the Tree of Life and the World Tree found in
almost every culture and is understood as the link between the conscious and
unconscious, the under-world and upper-world. By eating the apple, Eve made the
humans almost godlike. This myth might imply that the Divine is within us. This
understanding of myth as elaborated by Carl Jung, Joseph Campbell or Paul
Ricoeur, goes against the anti-historical or rational interpretations of myths,
that was fashionable few decades ago. As opposed to this view we know today
that we make myths and myths make us.
Campbell and Jung suggest that we create new myths
because the creative act allows us to delve into and become aware of the
unconscious which initially created symbols that have lasted a millennium and
have bound us physically and psychically. As Campbell holds the mythical image
“lies at the depth of the unconscious where man is no longer a distinct
individual, but his mind widens out and merges into the mind of mankind, not
the conscious mind, but the unconscious mind of mankind, where we are all the
same.”
The Purpose: Meaning-Making
Emile Durkheim, noted sociologist and mythologist,
explained that myth exists as a social institution that orders rituals,
economy, history and meaning structures of the society. He described it as the
unconscious of the society. In other words, myth is a global way of thinking
through which all social agendas emerge. Joseph Campbell said that we are all
living (or enacting) a myth and that we must figure out what our myth is, so
that we are not forced to live it against our will. He also warns that a
society that takes its myth literally is suffocating itself. Studying mythical
symbols is one form of bringing back the wonderfully divine, if not mystical,
experience of realizing that all life is connected, at the very least, on an
unconscious level. Joseph Campbell gives four purposes to myth: 1. To awaken
wonder by putting us back in touch with the child within. 2. To fill all
corners or niches of an image with the Mystery.
3. To validate social order. 4. To teach us how to conduct ourselves
during the stages of our lives. We can further add: 5. Myths enable us to live
the reality of contradictions meaningfully by giving us ideals to live by.
In summary, through myths we make sense of our
reality. It provides us with meanings, enables us to organize even the
contradictory experiences of our lives. It makes our lives bearable. It
explains to ourselves our own experiences. It justifies our actions to
ourselves and explains our failures and tragedies. Thus it has basically
mediating and a motivating functions. Myths also mediate the infinite through
the finite. It situates us in the vast cosmic and divine background, wherein we
can find the significance of our own selves. The puny, little human actions are
magnified and enriched because of the cosmic and divine significance attached
to it. They also motivate our actions. They enable us to live a meaningful life
within a wider horizon of significance. It is in such a horizon that we are
encouraged to act. Every action, originating from a mythical experience,
becomes unique and infinitely more meaningful at least for the actor of the
myth.
2.4 MYTH,
PHILOSOPHY AND SCIENCE
The two narrations above are meant to show the
similarity and difference between science and myth. True, for the contemporary
persons, science provides us with the best knowledge possible. The primitive
people used the best resources they had and came up with answers which did not
quiet satisfy them, but still provided them with meaning in life and made them
search further. In this process the
primitive people gave us the myths, which are truly powerful in shaping our
visions. None of us live according to
the myths of these people. But we have our own myths: answers we give ourselves
collectively and subconsciously when confronted with deep unresolved questions
of life, death, reality and destiny.
As such modern humans do have our own shared myths,
which most of the time we are not aware of. Only generations later, they will
be able to look at us and point out the
myths in our collective understanding. We do have our science, which explains
to us many of the mysteries of old. Science provides us with the best
explanation. But let us not forget that science of today may become the myth of
yesterday. As such myth and science serve the same purpose of explaining the
universe to ourselves, but at different levels. The methods they employ are
different. The answers they come up with are also diverse. That is because they
serve different domains of our enquiry.
Science is primarily empirical and provides us with facts, while myths
are based on the known facts and provide us with meaning. Such myths, when
elaborated and rationalized become philosophy.
Thus there is a movement from myth to philosophy and to science. Myths are
mostly factually not true but existentially meaningful. Philosophy tries to be
factually true and existentially meaningful. Science attempts to be factually
true and does not direct address the existential meaning. Myths provide us with
intuitive and existential meaning. Philosophy gives us rational meaning.
Science shows us empirical facts. Thus it is evident at as human beings we want
to know, to transform and to determine our collective destiny. As individuals
and group, we aspire to be related to our common origin and work towards our
common destiny, though all the resources at our hand: science, religion and
philosophy.
2.5 THE
GREEK QUEST FOR UNITY
In this section we attempt to show that basically
the Greek quest for unity, emanated from their inmost longing to be part of the
larger universe – both epistemologically and ontologically. So we shall trace
the deepest philosophical quest for unity as the central driving force for all
intellectual and even anthropological enterprises. As is generally presumed,
the earliest schools
of philosophy in the
West can be
traced to the sixth century B.C.
in Greece. Prominent among them were, first of all, the
Ionian School, the
Pythogorean School, the
Heraclitean School, and the Eleatic School. Right from the
beginning they had one quest
in common: the
search for one
singular essence that explained all reality.
Will Durant points out five unifying elements in the civilization of
the Greece that kept all its scattered
cities somehow connected: a common language, with local dialects; a common
intellectual life, in which only major
figures in literature,
philosophy, and science are
known far beyond their
political frontiers; a
common passion for
athletics, finding outlet in
municipal and interstate games;
love of beauty locally
expressed in forms of
art common to
all the Greek communities; and
a partly common
religious ritual and
belief.
Durant
goes on to
say that religion
divided the cities as
much as it united them. The city deity
was believed to be the preserver, defender, and strength of the city.
Just as the
father was the
priest in the
family, the chief
magistrate or archon was the
high priest of the
state religion in the
Greek city. Polytheism was accompanied by anthropomorphic mythologies.
Every craft, profession, and art had its divinity. Thus, polytheistic
religion pervaded almost
every facet of
Greek life. Homer’s Iliad and
Odyssey expresses the
view that the
gods control all human
events and the
one on the side of
the stronger god ultimately wins.
In such polytheism,
ethics mattered less. The
gods themselves are pictured as slaves of lust and passion. There is
no moral
order since there
is no single
point of reference
in the multiplicity of divinities. Each divinity is
a point of reference in itself. Whoever serves
that particular deity is
under its patronage
at the possibility of becoming an enemy of another
deity. Egotism, revenge, heroism, and
valor are extolled, as noted by Domenic Marbaniang.
The shift from multiple points of reference to a
consistent moral law that is
above even the
gods and determines the
state of the
world seems to
have first occurred in Hesiod. Writing
sometime in the
eighth century B.C., Hesiod dismissed the notion of fatality and of
the gods
as being morally inconsistent. Though
the gods control
nature, the moral
order which is
a product of
Zeus’ commands controls the
structure of the
universe and regulates its
process of changes. Thus, Hesiod’s
writings can be called the transitional bridge
between religious beliefs
and philosophical thinking. It
might have been this
transitional venture of
Hesiod that the Milesians
undertook, indicating a
substantial departure from
the poetry (myth) of Homer
and Hesiod and a movement
toward a scientific temper (Marbaniang).
According to Will Durant, the predecessor to
philosophy was a critical and
skeptical outlook produced by motley
of religions and cultures
that intersected each other
in the Greek
metropolises. Athens was
becoming a busy mart
and port that attracted varieties of
races and cults; thus, providing a context for
comparison, analysis and thought. As
Durant himself states: Traditions and
dogmas rub one
another down to a
minimum in such centers of varied intercourse; where there
are a thousand faiths we
are apt to
become sceptical of
them all. Probably
the traders were
the first sceptics;
they had seen too much to
believe too much; and the
general disposition of merchants
to classify all men as either
fools or knaves inclined them to
question every creed.
Durant’s speculative description of the Greek
environment in which philosophy took birth may not be wrong. It is natural to reason that two opposing views cannot be both true at the
same time. This points one to the
inescapability of reason in searching for truth. The necessity of
moral consistency might
even be felt
by the traders
for whom fidelity matters much. On the other hand,
people are seen as seeking to get nature
back into their control from
the hands of
the gods by
attempting to locate explanations
for natural events
in something other than the
gods. Such a unifying
singular was thought to be some kind of a primordial
substance. As Durant writes, ‘Men grew
bold enough to attempt natural explanations of processes and events
before attributed to supernatural
agencies and powers;
magic and ritual slowly
gave way to
science and control; and philosophy began.’
2.6 THE
IONIAN SCHOOL
As Marbaniang outlines, European philosophy is born
in the seaport town of Miletus, located
across the Aegean Sea from Athens, on
the western shores of Ionia in Asia Minor in around 585 B.C. This is
why the first
philosophers are also
referred to as Milesians
or Ionians. Ionia was a district of ancient Greece on the west coast
of Asia
Minor (present Turkey).
It comprised famous and important
cities like Ephesus,
Clazomenae, Erythrae, Colophon,
Smyrna, and Miletus. As Marbaniang notes, it is amazing to note how a religiously
steeped Ioniaians, who had earlier on produced Homer the
author of Iliad and Odyssey, should suddenly become very secular in
its search for wisdom;
thus, producing the first
of philosophers in Western history. However, as seen earlier, the quest for
control over nature might have been one
reason behind the search for some natural
explanation of the universe. As such the Ionians were searching for
a singular thing that was the essence of
all reality. If this essential thing
were rightly understood,
then all the
other things would also
be understood. Thus,
human being would be in possession
of a knowledge
that would serve as
an instrument to
both explain and control
natural processes.
The first of these Ionian philosophers is considered
to be Thales (624- 546 B.C.). Thales asked the question: What is everything
made of, or what stuff are
things composed of? His
contribution to thought was
the novel notion
that though all
things differ from
each other in several ways, there
is a basic similarity between them all and that the many are related to each other by the One.
For Thales, this one thing that united all
diversity and that was
foundational to all
physical reality was water.
According to him, it is from water that everything proceeds
and into which everything is
again resolved. Following Thales,
Aristotle in his metaphysics
observes that most
of the first philosophers thought the principles of matter were
the principles of
all things. In
other words, the
early metaphysicians were more concerned with the material cause of the
universe than with any of the other causes.
That of which all
things that are
consist, the first
from which they come
to be, the
last into which they
are resolved (the substance remaining, but changing in its
modifications), this they say is the element and this the principle
of things, and therefore
they think nothing is either generated or destroyed,
since this sort of entity
is always conserved,
as we say
Socrates neither comes
to be absolutely
when he comes to be beautiful
or musical, nor
ceases to be
when he loses these characteristics, because the
substratum, Socrates himself,
remains. Just so they
say nothing else
comes to be
or ceases to be;
for there must be some entity
– either one
or more than one
– from which all
other things come to be, it being
conserved.206
Aristotle
makes it clear
that most of
the first philosophers
thought that the material cause
was the one, indestructible, eternal substratum
to all things.
For Thales, this one,
uncreated, indestructible, eternal
substance or essence
of all things was
water. Aristotle opined that
Thales might have got
this notion from seeing that the
nutriment of all things is moist, and that heat itself is
generated from the moist and kept alive
by it; that the seeds of all things have a moist nature, and that water is the origin of the nature of
moist things (Marbaniang).
Anaximenes and Diogenes saw air as prior to water
and as the most primary of
the simple bodies.
Hippasus of Metapontium
and Heraclitus of
Ephesus said that fire
was the primary
principle. However, Empedocles
attempted to combine the above three with an addition of
a fourth, earth,
thus attributing finality to
the four elements:
water, air, fire,
and earth. Empedocles
argued that these always
remain and do not
come to be,
except that they
come to be
more or fewer,
being aggregated into one and segregated out of one.
Aristotle, however, questioned this restricting of ultimate
reality to material
causes only and
disregarding the effective
cause and final cause of things.
He argued that if material causes, like air or
water, are the
final essentialities, then
the world cannot come
to be good or
beautiful, and is
thus devoid of any
goal or purpose
for existence. In his words:
…it is not likely either that fire or earth or any
such element should be the
reason why things manifest
goodness and beauty both in their
being and in their coming to be, or that
those thinkers should have supposed it was; nor again could it be right
to entrust so
great a matter
to spontaneity and chance. When one man said, then, that
reason was present – as in animals, so
throughout nature – as the cause of order
and of all arrangement,
he seemed like
a sober man in
contrast with the random talk of his predecessors.209
The Ionian philosophers did not seem to consider the problem of the how
or why of the universe.
In terms of
Aristotelian thinking, such metaphysics falls
short of authoritative
science because “the
science which knows
to what end each
thing must be done
is the most
authoritative of the
sciences…and this end is
the good of that
thing, and in general
the supreme good in
the whole of
nature.”210 Thus, according to Aristotle, it is not just the
discovery of the material cause but also
the discovery of the efficient and final causes that is important in this search for ultimate reality. This
need to unravel the other causes
manifests itself though naively in
theories that regard elements like
fire “having a nature which fits it to move things” as the first
principle.
The basic drive was, however, to find out that one
element that united and was fundamental
to all of
nature. This doesn’t
mean that there
weren’t some who
seemingly posited a pluralistic
foundation of the
universe as can
be seen in the
later Thracian materialistic
schools of Leucippus and Democritus. But
even in the atomic
theory of Democritus, the
atoms are all
made of the
same matter though
they differ in shape, size,
weight, sequence, and position. They are minute, invisible,
indivisible, indestructible, and eternal.211 The
quest for the
One cannot be
evaded in latter thinking.
The Ionians, thus, can
be considered to initiate the
quest for the One in Metaphysics.
In summary, the Ionian philosophers beginning with
Thales searched for the one,
fundamental, element or principle that united all of nature. The philosophers disagreed among themselves
as to whether this first principle
was water or air or fire until
Empedocles decided to regard all three together with
a fourth, earth,
as the four
elements out of which all things come. The next question,
inevitably, was “what is that element
that was
the quintessence of
the four elements?”
The search for the
One, thus, was
inescapable. The One
out of which the
many proceeded was considered to
be eternal. However,
the early Ionians
left the question of efficient causality and purpose out of their
theories. Though some would not
consider this to
be a major
problem at all,
Aristotle thought this to be a real problem. How can chance produce the
effects of beauty
and goodness in nature?
There has to
be an efficient and a
final cause of the universe.
The universe cannot
be a free lunch. This led Anaxagoras212 to
conclude that the cosmos is the
result of an
eternal governing principle
called nous (intelligence, reason) that
brings order out
of the chaotic
sea of atoms
in the universe.
This, however, leads
to two different
eternal causes: the
material cause being
the atoms and
the efficient cause
being reason. Thus, the quest for
the unity in diversity of matter led to the quest for the efficient cause of all things in
general.
The Ionian speculation of an eternal first material
principle alludes to the following consequences, as summarised by
Marbaniang:
1. Something cannot
come out of
nothing. Therefore, something must have eternally existed.
2. Something
cannot produce its unlike; therefore, all things are made up of that something.
3. Thales (according to
Aristotle’s guess): All
things grow in moist; therefore, water is the source of
all things.
4. Anaximenes and Diogenes:
Air is prior
to water; therefore,
air is the most primary of the simple bodies.
5. Anaxagoras: Matter is
composed of infinite minute
atoms which are chaotic in
nature. Order out of chaos can only
be created by mind. Therefore, nous (an eternal intelligence) is the
author of unity
and order in the
universe. Since something
cannot come out
of nothing the material
cause “atoms” are
eternal. Since chaos
is natural, reason
must be the eternal author of order in the
universe.
Consequently,
the universe itself
is materialistically eternal
in Ionian philosophy. However,
none of the
Ionian philosophers were able
to sufficiently explain how
the primordial elements
that they proposed
were the basic foundation of the universe.
2.7 TOWARDS A GRAND UNIFICATION THEORY OR
THEORY OF EVERYTHING
From the Ionians of ancient Greek we are making a
tremendous leap to the contemporary scientists. We try to show that similar
passion has been guiding the contemporary scientist to search for an ultimate
theory that unifies everything. Contemporary physics of the early Universe is
at the boundary of astronomy and philosophy since we do not currently have a
complete theory that unifies all the fundamental forces of Nature at the moment
of Big Bang. In addition, there is no possibility of linking observation or
experimentation of early Universe physics to our theories (i.e. it is not
possible to `build' another Universe). Our theories are rejected or accepted
based on simplicity and aesthetic grounds, plus their power of prediction,
rather than an appeal to empirical results. Our physics today can explain most
of the evolution of the Universe after the Planck time (approximately 10-43
seconds after the Big Bang). One of the
reasons our physics is incomplete during the Planck era is its lack of understanding of the unification of
the forces of Nature during this time. At high energies and temperatures, the
forces of Nature become symmetric. This means the forces resemble each other
and become similar in strength, i.e. they unify. When the forces break from
unification (as the Universe expands and cools) interesting things happen and
we have the present universe..
The term Grand Unified Theory or GUT, refers to any
of several similar models in today’s particle physics in which at high energy
scales where all the forces are merged into one single interaction. The
information about models of grand
unification is obtained through indirect means. The Large Hadron Collider
(LHC) being operated at CERN,
Geneva, is such an attempt. It is a
gigantic scientific instrument near Geneva, where it spans the border between
Switzerland and France about 100 m underground. It is a particle accelerator
used by physicists to study the smallest known particles – the fundamental
building blocks of all things. It will revolutionise our understanding, from
the minuscule world deep within atoms to the vastness of the Universe.
Two beams of subatomic particles called 'hadrons' –
either protons or lead ions –travel in opposite directions inside the circular
accelerator, gaining energy with every lap. Physicists will use the LHC to
recreate the conditions just after the Big Bang, by colliding the two beams
head-on at very high energy. Teams of physicists from around the world will
analyse the particles created in the collisions using special detectors in a
number of experiments dedicated to the LHC. There are many theories as to what
will result from these collisions, but what's for sure is that a brave new
world of physics will emerge from the new accelerator, as knowledge in particle
physics goes on to describe the workings of the Universe. For decades, the
Standard Model of particle physics has served physicists well as a means of
understanding the fundamental laws of Nature, but it does not tell the whole
story. Only experimental data using the higher energies reached by the LHC can
push knowledge forward, challenging those who seek confirmation of established
knowledge, and those who dare to dream beyond the paradigm. Unifying gravity
with the other three interactions (electro-magnetic force, weak force and
nuclear force) would form a theory of everything (TOE). Grand Unification is
reminiscent of the unification of electric and magnetic forces by Maxwell's
theory of electromagnetism in the 19th century, but its physical implications
and mathematical structure are qualitatively different.
2.8 EINSTEIN’S PERENNIAL QUEST FOR UNITY
Buried in Albert Einstein’s mail one spring day in
1953 lay a letter from an ordinary student, a 20-year-old high school dropout
named John Moffat. Two totally different
persons! Moffat was an
impoverished artist and self-taught physicist. Einstein was a mythic figure - the world’s most famous scientist. In his
later years, Einstein had become increasingly isolated from the physics
community, refusing to embrace the strange but powerful theory of quantum
mechanics—with its particles that are also waves and that exist in no specific
place until they’re observed. Nature, he argued, couldn’t be so perverse. So
for nearly 30 years he had pursued a quixotic goal: the creation of a unified
field theory to describe all the forces of nature (Tim Folger). That was the
occasion for Moffat’s letter. He thought he could offer Einstein some
constructive criticism. “I wrote him to say that I wasn’t happy about what he
was doing,” Moffat recalls. And he was privileged to get a reply. “Dear Mr. Moffat, Our situation is the
following. We are standing in front of a closed box which we cannot open, and
we try hard to discover about what is and is not in it.” That closed box is the
universe, and Einstein has been trying
his best to open it. But, according to
many of his colleagues he had contributed almost nothing of importance to
physics for almost 20 years, chasing a unified theory. Did he squander his
genius by chasing vainly after an ultimate theory? Though that is the generally accepted view,
at least a few physicists now argue that Einstein was far ahead of his time,
raising questions that will challenge researchers for decades. Moffat, who later went on to become a
theoretical physicist.: “This, of course, is erroneous. Einstein never wasted
his time.” (Tim Folger)
Einstein’s split with mainstream physics came at the
very height of his career. In 1927, when he was 48, the world’s leading
physicists gathered at a conference in Brussels to debate an issue that remains
contentious to this day: What does quantum mechanics have to say about reality?
Einstein had won the Nobel Prize in physics for research that showed that light
consists of particles of energy—research that laid the groundwork for quantum
mechanics. Yet he dismissed the new theory out of hand. At the conference, he clashed with the great
Danish physicist Niels Bohr, starting a quarrel
that would last until Einstein’s death in 1955.
Einstein’s work was not without promise, at first.
He was attempting to unite the force of gravity with the force of
electromagnetism, and the two forces are similar in many ways. Einstein spent the last two decades of his life
refining this idea. At the same time, he tried to iron out what he saw as
problems in his general theory of relativity. In cases where gravity was
extremely strong, his theories broke down. Moreover, they seemed to permit the
formation of what we now call black holes — objects of such enormous density
that their gravity traps even light. “Einstein didn’t like black holes,” Moffat
says. “The real motivation for generalizing his gravity theory was to see if he
could find, as he called them, ‘everywhere regular solutions’ that fit the
equations.” Such solutions, Einstein hoped, would eliminate black holes
entirely. So , as Moffart says, “Einstein went into denial, because he had
invested so much time in this—years!” Near the end of his life, Einstein realized
that he wouldn’t live to complete his work. “I have locked myself into quite
hopeless scientific problems,” he wrote, “the more so since, as an elderly man,
I have remained estranged from the society here.”
In the 1930s, when Einstein began his work on a
unified field theory, physicists believed that there were only two universal
forces that the theory would have to unite: gravity and electromagnetism. They
have since learned that there are two other fundamental forces as well, a
strong force that binds together atomic nuclei and a weak force that governs
radioactive decay. “Einstein defined what later became a fundamental problem in
physics,” says Carlo Rovelli, a theoretical physicist in
France, as quoted by Tim Folger.
After about fifty years, Einstein’s once-lonely quest engages thousands
of physicists around the world, most of them working on an ambitious physics
framework known as string theory. Although this work is grounded in string
theory and it relies heavily on some of
the same components that Einstein used.
But the researchers are still cautious. Moffat says that it is “pure hubris,” to claim there
is an ultimate theory of everything. “There’s always something new on the
horizon, and then everything starts all over again.”
The general theory of relativity was developed in
defiance of centuries of physics. It consumed Einstein for 11 years—from 1905
to 1916—and in the end was proved triumphantly correct. It’s no wonder the
memory of that achievement sustained him in later years. In 1953, when the
letter from John Moffat found its way to Princeton, Einstein was still doing
what he had always done—asking big questions and looking for big answers:
looking for simplicity and searching for one unifying principle that grounds
everything.
2.9 CONCLUSION: PHILOSOPHICAL QUEST
Philosophy comes from the Greek for "love of
wisdom," giving us two important starting points: love (or passion) and
wisdom (knowledge, understanding). Philosophy is to be pursued without passion
and commitment, since it involves us totally. The primitive Neadnderthals, the
Ionians, the contemporary scientists and Einstein, all of them had this goal:
to make sense of our lives and of the
world around us. This perennial goal could be attempted through different ways
– philosophies, myths, religions and sciences. Because we are human, we just
cannot cease to explore and question. Thus the
passionate search of human beings everywhere to make sense of themselves
in the world leads us directly to philosophy and religion and indirectly to
sciences. Thus the original unity calls
us back to discover our own identity and sense of belonging in this
universe. In this process we grow,
evolve and discover meaning.
2.10
LET US SUM UP
We have seem how humans try to make sense of the
world by trying to return to an original
unity, which always remains an ideal.
The search for to rediscover that original unity keeps us move forward
as human beings.
2.11 KEY WORDS
Myths: Philosophically myths are stories, through
which we make sense of our reality. It provides us with meanings, enables us to
organize even the contradictory experiences of our lives. It makes our lives
bearable.
GUT: The term Grand Unified Theory or GUT, refers to
any of several similar models in today’s particle physics in which at high
energy scales where all the forces are merged into one single interaction. At
this level, all the forces become one and so we have a grand unification of
everything.
UNIT 3 EVOLUTION OF THE DISTINCT METHODS OF SCIENCE
Contents
3.0 Objectives
3.1 Introduction
3.2 Definition
of Scientific method
3.3 The
Scientific Method
3.4 Hypothesis
3.5 Theory-Dependence
of Observation
3.6 Scope of Science and Scientific Methods
3.7 Prevalent
Mistakes in Applying the Scientific Method
3.8 Let
Us Sum Up
3.9 Key
Words
3.10 Further
Readings and References
3.0 OBJECTIVES
The main object of this Unit is to give a pre-taste
of different methods of science. In this unit we shall try to give a definition
of scientific method, both etymological and real; then let us proceed to know
how different scientific methods developed in the history of science. Further
let us discuss about the scientific method and its components, the scope and
importance of scientific methods in our life and how to use the different methods
of science in our day to day life. At
the end we come to know that a scientific method consists of the collection of
data through observation and experimentation, and the formulation and testing
of hypotheses and it enhances the life of humanity in different. Thus by the
end of this Unit you should be able: to have a basic understanding of methods
of science; to know the development of the scientific methods; to understand
the all-comprehensive character of scientific methods; to know the importance of
scientific methods both at the theoretical and practical levels. to know how to
apply scientific methods in experiments.
3.1 INTRODUCTION
The term “science” is used to identify the various
sciences, or domains of activity. First to be recognized were the natural
sciences, such as physics, astronomy, chemistry, geology, and biology. The
human and social sciences have also been termed sciences. Some of these are
psychology, economics, education, geography, and sociology. Science has
contributed much to the development of human being. By using scientific
principles, man has pulled back the curtain of ignorance and advanced the
quality of life. The essence of science is the scientific method where a
hypothesis is tested by experiment. Instead of endless philosophical
discussions to prove a point, experiment becomes the final arbitrator of truth
and a successful approach. To make an experiment we need to have distinct
methods to prove a point or truth. The so called "method" is so
engrained in our way of approaching science today that we tend to take it for
granted. The scientific method is the process by which scientists, collectively
and over time, endeavour to construct an accurate representation of the world.
Let us venture into the exploration of different scientific methods in this
unit.
3.2 DEFINITION
OF SCIENTIFIC METHOD
The scientific method or process is fundamental to
the scientific investigation and acquisition of new knowledge based upon
physical evidence. Science manages new assertions about our world with
theories, hypotheses and observations. Predictions from these theories are
tested by experiment. If a prediction turns out correct, the theory survives,
but if a prediction fails the theory fails. The scientific method is
essentially an extremely cautious means of building a supportable, evidenced
understanding of our world. A scientific method consists of the collection of
data through observation and experimentation, and the formulation and testing
of hypotheses. Scientific method refers to a body of techniques for
investigating phenomena, acquiring new knowledge, or correcting and integrating
previous knowledge. To be termed scientific, a method of inquiry must be based
on gathering observable, empirical and measurable evidence subject to specific principles
of reasoning. The scientific method is the basic method, guide, and system by
which we originate, refine, extend, and apply knowledge in all fields.
The word science has its origins in the Latin verb
scire, meaning "to know." Although, one can "know" through
tenacity, authority, faith, intuition, or science, the method of science or the
scientific method is distinct in its notion of intersubjective certification.
In other words, it should be possible for other investigators to ascertain the
truth content of scientific explanations. "Scientific knowledge thus rests
on the bedrock of empirical testability". Empirical replication depends on
a comparison of "objective" observations of different researchers
studying the phenomenon.
• The
Scientific Method has Four Steps
• Observation
and description of a phenomenon or group of phenomena.
• Formulation
of a hypothesis to explain the phenomena.
• Use
of the hypothesis to predict the existence of other phenomena, or to predict
quantitatively the results of new observations.
• Performance
of experimental tests of the predictions by several independent experimenters
and properly performed experiments.
3.3 THE
EVOLUTION OF SCIENTIFIC METHODS
Modern western science had its beginnings with the
Greeks, who conceived the revolutionary idea that the universe was a kind of
machine governed by inflexible laws. This idea became the mechanistic model of
science. The Greek philosophers devoted themselves to the task of discovering,
through intellectual reasoning alone, the laws of the universe. Therefore
Modern scientific thought, therefore, evolved from the Greek philosophers who
were influenced by the Egyptians, Babylonians, and Assyrians. Their greatest
successes were in the field of geometry. The Greek successes are attributable
to two techniques: abstraction and generalization. So successful were these
techniques in developing mathematical theory that the concepts were extended to
other disciplines, but with much less success. However, the process of looking
for absolute truth through reasoning alone was so ingrained in the Greek
thinking patterns that they ignored the experiential evidence which was
contrary to their elegant theorems and proofs.
The Renaissance thinkers, however, brought a fresh
outlook. The most famous turning point came in 1543 when the Polish astronomer
Copernicus published a book which proposed the sun, not the earth, as the
centre of the universe. Although his hypothesis had been put forth in 200 B.C.,
it was in 1543 diametrically opposed to the assumptions of the Greeks and the
teachings of the Church. He caused a great uproar within the intellectual
world. It was left to Galileo to have the audacity to test the Greek theories.
His most famous experiment probably never happened, but it makes a good story.
Galileo supposedly dropped two cannon balls of different weights from the
leaning tower of Pisa to prove Aristotle's theory that the heavier body would
hit the ground first. The resounding thump of the two spheres hitting the
ground simultaneously killed Aristotelian physics and elevated inductive
reasoning as a scientific tool. Inductive reasoning begins with observations
and derives generalizations (axioms) from the observations; whereas deductive
reasoning, the method of the Greeks, begins with generalizations and proceeds
to predict observations. But it was the recognition during the Renaissance that
no amount of deductive reasoning can render a generalization completely and
absolutely valid that turned the Greek philosophy upside down.
Francis Bacon offered four steps for scientific
work: observe, measure, explain, and verify. And then there was René Descartes
who also gave four rules for his method to find the truth in 1961. The rules
are as follows:
• Never
to accept anything for true which I do not clearly know to be such.
• Divide
each of the difficulties under examination into as many parts as possible.
• Begin
with the simplest and easiest and then work step by step to the more complex.
• Make
enumerations so complete and reviews so general that I might be assured that
nothing is omitted.
The essentially contemporaneous writings of Galileo,
Bacon, and Descartes revolutionized scientific procedures and gave rise to what
has been called the scientific method. The collective ideas which Galileo,
Bacon, and Descartes brought to scientific endeavour have changed somewhat
since the 17th century. By the 19th century, the method developed into six
steps, and in the 20th century the method developed into seven, namely:
• Pose
a question about nature, not necessarily as the result of an observation.
• Collect
the pertinent, observable evidence.
• Formulate
an explanatory hypothesis, defining relevant assumptions.
• Deduce
its implications.
• Test
all of the implications experimentally.
• Accept,
reject, or modify the hypothesis based upon the experimental results.
• Define
its range of applicability.
The scientific method's essential elements are
iterations, recursions interleavings, and orderings of the following four
steps:
• Characterization
• Hypothesis
(a theoretical, hypothetical explanation)
• Prediction
(logical deduction from the hypothesis)
• Experiment
(test of all of the above)
Iteration is the repetition of a process, it is a
repetition in a specific form of repetition with a mutable state and recursion
is a particular way of specifying or constructing a class of objects with the
help of a reference to other objects of the class: a recursive definition
defines objects in terms of the already defined objects of the class.
Interleaving is a way to arrange data in a non-contiguous way to increase
performance. Orderings formalizes the intuitive concept of an ordering,
sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set.
Characterization
The scientific method depends upon a careful
characterization of the subject of the investigation. Here the subject may also
be called the problem or the unknown. Observation demands careful measurement
and the use of operational definitions of relevant concepts. Formally, these
terms have exact meanings which do not necessarily correspond with their
natural language usage. For example, mass and weight are quite distinct
concepts. New theories may also arise upon realizing that certain terms had not
previously been clearly defined. For example, Albert Einstein's first paper on
relativity begins by defining simultaneity and the means for determining
length. These ideas were skipped over by Newton with, "I do not define
time, space, place and motion, as being well known to all." Einstein's
paper then demonstrates that these widely accepted ideas were invalid.
3.4 HYPOTHESIS
A hypothesis is a suggested explanation of a
phenomenon, or alternately a reasoned proposal suggesting a possible
correlation between or among a set of phenomena. A hypothesis includes a
suggested explanation of the subject. It will generally provide a causal
explanation or propose some correlation. Observations have the general form of
existential statements, stating that some particular instance of the phenomenon
being studied has some characteristic. Causal explanations have the general
form of universal statements, stating that every instance of the phenomenon has
a particular characteristic. It is not deductively valid to infer a universal
statement from any series of particular observations. This is the problem of
induction. Scientists use whatever they can, their own creativity, ideas from
other fields, induction, systematic guessing, etc to imagine possible
explanations for a phenomenon under study. There are no definitive guidelines
for the production of new hypotheses. The history of science is filled with
stories of scientists claiming a "flash of inspiration", or a hunch,
which then motivated them to look for evidence to support or refute their idea.
Michael Polanyi made such creativity the centerpiece of his discussion of
methodology.
Prediction from the Hypothesis
A useful hypothesis will enable predictions, by
deductive reasoning that can be experimentally assessed. If results contradict
the predictions, then the hypothesis under test is incorrect or incomplete and
requires either revision or abandonment. If results confirm the predictions,
then the hypothesis might be correct but is still subject to further testing.
Einstein's theory of General Relativity makes several specific predictions
about the observable structure of space-time, such as a prediction that light
bends in a gravitational field and that the amount of bending depends in a
precise way on the strength of that gravitational field. Observations made
during a 1919 solar eclipse supported General Relativity rather than Newtonian
gravitation.
Predictions refer to experiment designs with a
currently unknown outcome; the classic example was Edmund Halley's prediction
of the year of return of Halley's comet which returned after his death. A
prediction differs from a consequence, which does not necessarily bear a
time-dependent connotation. Thus, one consequence of General Relativity, which
Einstein deduced, was the size of the precession of the perihelion of the orbit
of the planet Mercury. The observed value, on the order of 42 arc-seconds per
century, was one of the pieces of evidence for Einstein's characterization of
his theory of General Relativity. This consequence was known to Einstein, in
contrast to his predictions, in which he had enough confidence to publish.
Experiment
Once a prediction is made, an experiment is designed
to test it. The experiment may seek either confirmation or falsification of the
hypothesis. Yet an experiment is not an absolute requirement. In observation
based fields of science actual experiments must be designed differently than
for the classical laboratory based sciences. Scientists assume an attitude of
openness and accountability on the part of those conducting an experiment.
Detailed recordkeeping is essential, to aid in recording and reporting on the
experimental results, and providing evidence of the effectiveness and integrity
of the procedure. They will also assist in reproducing the experimental results.
Integrity may be augmented by the introduction of a control. Two virtually
identical experiments are run, in only one of which the factor being tested is
varied. This serves to further isolate any causal phenomena. For example in
testing a drug it is important to carefully test that the supposed effect of
the drug is produced only by the drug itself. Doctors may do this with a
double-blind study: two virtually identical groups of patients are compared,
one of which receives the drug and one of which receives a placebo. Neither the
patients nor the doctor know who is getting the real drug, isolating its
effects.
Once an experiment is complete, a researcher
determines whether the results or data gathered are what was predicted. If the
experimental conclusions fail to match the predictions/hypothesis, then one
returns to the failed hypothesis and re-iterates the process. If the
experiments appear "successful" i.e. fits the hypothesis and then its
details become published so that others may reproduce the same experimental
results.
3.5 THEORY-DEPENDENCE OF OBSERVATION
The scientific method depends on observation, in defining
the subject under investigation and in performing experiments. Observation
involves perception, and so is a cognitive process. That is, one does not make
an observation passively, but is actively involved in distinguishing the thing
being observed from surrounding sensory data. Therefore, observations depend on
some underlying understanding of the way in which the world functions, and that
understanding may influence what is perceived, noticed, or deemed worthy of
consideration. Empirical observation is
supposedly used to determine the acceptability of some hypothesis within a
theory. When someone claims to have made an observation, it is reasonable to
ask them to justify their claim. Such a justification must itself make
reference to the theory - operational definitions and hypotheses - in which the
observation is embedded. That is, the observation is a component of the theory
that also contains the hypothesis it either verifies or falsifies. But this
means that the observation cannot serve as a neutral arbiter between competing
hypotheses. Observation could only do this "neutrally" if it were
independent of the theory.
Thomas Kuhn denied that it is ever possible to
isolate the theory being tested from the influence of the theory in which the
observations are grounded. He argued that observations always rely on a
specific paradigm, and that it is not possible to evaluate competing paradigms
independently. By "paradigm" he meant, essentially, a logically
consistent "portrait" of the world, one that involves no logical
contradictions. More than one such logically consistent construct can each
paint a usable likeness of the world, but it is pointless to pit them against
each other, theory against theory. Neither is a standard by which the other can
be judged. Instead, the question is which "portrait" is judged by
some set of people to promise the most in terms of “puzzle solving”. For Kuhn,
the choice of paradigm was sustained by, but not ultimately determined by,
logical processes. The individual's choice between paradigms involves setting
two or more “portraits" against the world and deciding which likeness is
most promising. In the case of a general acceptance of one paradigm or another,
Kuhn believed that it represented the consensus of the community of scientists.
Acceptance or rejection of some paradigm is, he argued, more a social than a
logical process. That observation is embedded in theory does not mean that
observations are irrelevant to science. Scientific understanding derives from
observation, but the acceptance of scientific statements is dependent on the
related theoretical background or paradigm as well as on observation.
Coherentism and skepticism offer alternatives to foundationalism for dealing
with the difficulty of grounding scientific theories in something more than
observations.
Demarcation
Scientific Method is touted as one way of
determining which disciplines are scientific and which are not. Those which
follow the scientific method might be considered sciences; those that do not
are not. That is, method might be used as the criterion of demarcation between
science and non-science. If it is not possible to articulate a definitive
method, then it may also not be possible to articulate a definitive distinction
between science and non-science, between science and pseudo-science, and
between scientists and non-scientists. Feyerabend denies there is a scientific
method, and in his book Against Method argues that scientific progress is not
the result of the application of any particular method. In essence, he says
that anything goes. Thus the demarcation helps us to know the divergence of
scientific methods and non- scientific methods.
3.6 SCOPE OF SCIENCE AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS
The scopes of scientific methods are massive and
very useful in our life. Scientific method is not a recipe. It requires
intelligence, imagination, and creativity. It is also an ongoing cycle,
constantly developing more useful, accurate and comprehensive models and
methods. Science is not merely a collection of facts, concepts, and useful
ideas about nature, or even the systematic investigation of nature, although
both are common definitions of science. Science is a method of investigating
nature, a way of knowing about nature that discovers reliable knowledge about
it. In other words, science is a method of discovering reliable knowledge about
nature. There are other methods of discovering and learning knowledge about
nature .These other knowledge methods or systems will be discussed below in
contradistinction to science, but science is the only method that results in
the acquisition of reliable knowledge.
Reliable knowledge is knowledge that has a high
probablility of being true because its veracity has been justified by a
reliable method. Reliable knowledge is sometimes called justified true belief,
to distinguish reliable knowledge from belief that is false and unjustified or
even true but unjustified. The important distinction that should be made is
whether one's knowledge or beliefs are true and, if true, are justifiably true.
Every person has knowledge or beliefs, but not all of each person's knowledge
is reliably true and justified. In fact, most individuals believe in things
that are untrue or unjustified or both: most people possess a lot of unreliable
knowledge and, what's worse, they act on that knowledge. Other ways of knowing,
and there are many in addition to science, are not reliable because their
discovered knowledge is not justified. Science is a method that allows a person
to possess, with the highest degree of certainty possible, reliable knowledge,
justified true belief about nature. The method used to justify scientific
knowledge, and thus make it reliable, is called the scientific method. The
scientific method has proven to be the most reliable and successful method of
thinking in human history, and it is quite possible to use scientific thinking
in other human endeavours.
Importance of Scientific method
It is of great national importance that the
scientific method, which is not just for scientists but is really a general
problem solving method for everyone. Centuries of study, debate, and
experimentation has established that the best of all methods of obtaining and
originating reliable knowledge in all fields is the scientific method. The
scientific method is the guide to the mental activities and systems needed to
solve the complex competitiveness problems. It is, rather, an attitude, a
philosophy, an ethic to guide the process humans use to make sense out of the
deluge of sensory experience which is the foundation of our progression to
Paradise. As it has evolved, the method is so pervasive that it can be used in
any discipline, forcing the theoretician and experimentalist to complement one
another. It bridges the gap between ideas and facts, between speculation and
experience, between chaos and order. It allows the sorting of the relevant and
useful from the impertinent and delusive. It allows the exploitation of those
rare moments of intuitive inspiration and insight which have proven so
indispensable to scientific progress. However, the method cannot replace
intuition, conjure good luck, dissuade misuse, or speed the slow process of
intellectual growth and seasoning.
3.7 PREVALENT
MISTAKES IN APPLYING THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD
In applying scientific methods we inclined to make
some mistakes. The scientific method attempts to minimize the influence of the
scientist's bias on the outcome of an experiment. That is, when testing a
hypothesis or a theory, the scientist may have a preference for one outcome or another,
and it is important that this preference not bias the results or their
interpretation. The most fundamental error is to mistake the hypothesis for an
explanation of a phenomenon, without performing experimental tests. Sometimes
"common sense" and "logic" tempt us into believing that no
test is needed. There are numerous examples of this, dating from the Greek
philosophers to the present day. To ignore or rule out data which do not
support the hypothesis is another common mistake. Ideally, the experimenter is
open to the possibility that the hypothesis is correct or incorrect. Sometimes,
however, a scientist may have a strong belief that the hypothesis is true or
false, or feels internal or external pressure to get a specific result. In that
case, there may be a psychological tendency to find "something
wrong", such as systematic effects, with data which do not support the
scientist's expectations, while data which do agree with those expectations may
not be checked as carefully. The lesson is that all data must be handled in the
same way.
One more common mistake arises from the failure to
estimate quantitatively systematic errors. There are many examples of
discoveries which were missed by experimenters whose data contained a new
phenomenon, but who explained it away as a systematic background. Conversely,
there are many examples of alleged "new discoveries" which later
proved to be due to systematic errors not accounted for by the
"discoverers." In a field where there is active experimentation and
open communication among members of the scientific community, the biases of
individuals or groups may cancel out, because experimental tests are repeated
by different scientists who may have different biases. In addition, different
types of experimental setups have different sources of systematic errors. Over
a period spanning a variety of experimental tests, a consensus develops in the
community as to which experimental results have stood the test of time. The
scientific method attempts to minimize the influence of bias or prejudice in
the experimenter when testing a hypothesis or a theory. Let us realize this and
try to learn the correct way of applying scientific methods.
3.8 LET US SUM UP
We have learnt about the what, why and how of
different scientific methods and the evolution of different scientific methods
also have shed light upon how to use them in our experiments, decision making
and problem solving in our day to day life. The scientific method is
intricately associated with science, the process of human inquiry that pervades
the modern era on many levels. While the method appears simple and logical in
description, there is perhaps no more complex question than that of knowing how
we come to know things. The scientific method distinguishes science from other
forms of explanation because of its requirement of systematic experimentation.
We have also tried to point out some of the criteria and practices developed by
scientists to reduce the influence of individual or social bias on scientific
findings. Further investigations of the scientific method and other aspects of
scientific practice may be found in the references listed below.
3.9 KEY
WORDS
Hypothesis is a suggested explanation of a
phenomenon, or alternately a reasoned proposal suggesting a possible
correlation between or among a set of phenomena.
Iteration is the repetition of a process. It is a
repetition in a specific form of repetition with a mutable state.
Recursion is a particular way of specifying or
constructing a class of objects with the help of a reference to other objects
of the class: a recursive definition defines objects in terms of the already
defined objects of the class.
Interleaving is a way to arrange data in a
non-contiguous way to increase performance. Orderings formalizes the intuitive
concept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set.
UNIT 4 RELATION
OF SCIENTIFIC AND PHILOSOPHICAL METHODS
Contents
4.0 Objectives
4.1
Introduction
4.2 Definitions
of Scientific and Philosophical method
4.3 Philosophical
method
4.4 Scientific
method
4.5 The
relation
4.6 The
Importance of Philosophical and scientific methods
4.7 Let
Us Sum Up
4.8 Key
Words
4.9 Further
Readings and References
4.0 OBJECTIVES
The main objective of this unit is to analyse the
relation of scientific and philosophical methods. In this process we shall try
to give a detailed account and definition of philosophical methods and
scientific methods. Thus after knowing the two different methods we shall
examine the relation of scientific and philosophical methods. In this section
let us also know about the relation of science and philosophy. Finally
clarifying the importance of scientific and philosophical methods is yet
another objective of this unit of study.
Thus by the end of this Unit you should be able:
• to
have a basic understanding of scientific and philosophical methods;
• to
know the relation of scientific and philosophical methods;
• to
relate it with day – to – day life;
• to
understand the all-comprehensive character of scientific and philosophical
methods;
• to
know the importance of scientific and philosophical methods both at the
theoretical and practical levels.
4.1 INTRODUCTION
Science and philosophy, I would say, the two pillars
of the universe that make it revolve efficiently. Philosophy is the study of
and the attempt to gain knowledge and truth.
It is a way of looking at things.
It is a collection of ideas and assumptions that are used to interpret
reality. It is “the rational
investigation of the truths and principles of being, knowledge, or
conduct.” If we understand that the
scientific method is a way of attaining truth, then it falls under the
definition of philosophy. Science and philosophy are on the way to finding the
truth. In this journey both of them use their own methods to know the truth. In
this unit we are going to analyse what is philosophical method and scientific
method and how these two methods are related to each other.
4.2 DEFINITIONS OF SCIENTIFIC AND
PHILOSOPHICAL METHOD
Philosophical method is the study and description of
how to do philosophy. A method of doing some activity is a systematic or
patterned way of doing that activity. So a method of doing philosophy, or a
philosophical method, is a systematic or patterned way of answering
philosophical questions. The scientific method is used in science as a means of
gaining understanding about the physical universe. Scientific method is the
basic steps that scientists follow in uncovering facts and solving scientific
problems. Scientific method refers to a body of techniques for investigating
phenomena, acquiring new knowledge, or correcting and integrating previous
knowledge. The scientific method is essentially an extremely cautious means of
building a supportable, evidenced understanding of our world. Now we know the
definitions of scientific and philosophical methods. In the next section let us
study the philosophical method.
4.3 PHILOSOPHICAL METHOD
Philosophy is the study of and the attempt to gain
knowledge and truth. It is a way of
looking at things. It is a collection of
ideas and assumptions that are used to interpret reality. Philosophy is a quest
for the best arguments. A good argument is a clear, organized, sound statement,
the reasons which cure the original doubts in a problem. Philosophy is
distinguished by the methods that philosophers follow in tackling philosophical
questions. Philosophical method involves a commitment to reason and argument as
a source of knowledge.
Methodology process: Methodology process is a
systematic process of doubting or being skeptical about the truth of one's
beliefs. In methodology process methodic doubt which is a systematic process of
being doubting the truth of one's beliefs, arguments to support the solutions
and dialectic, which is presenting the solution and arguments for criticism by
other philosophers, and help them judge their own, are involved.
Doubt and the sense of wonder: Philosophy begins at
wonder. Philosophy time and again begins with some simple doubts about accepted
beliefs. We get the initial impulse to philosophize from the suspicion that we
do not fully understand, and have not fully justified, even our most basic
beliefs about the world.
Formulate questions and problems: The next step in
the philosophical method is to formulate our doubts in questions to be answered
or problems to be solved. Questioning is the first weapon of a philosopher with
which one works. The more clearly the question or problem is stated, the easier
it will be to identify critical issues, the assessment of which undergirds any
genuine progress in coming to some sort of resolution. Here it is not enough to
wonder at doubt but to state as clearly as possible what exactly the source of
doubt is. Let us take the problem of freedom and determinism. We can say,
suppose that, the universe operates according to deterministic causal laws,
that is, for everything that happens, there are some laws which made it
necessary that thing, and only that thing happened and as a result all events
are determined. Suppose also this general principle applies to our choices. Our
choices are events in, parts of, the natural world, and so we should fully
expect to find a complete causal explanation of those too, explaining why we
had to make those choices and no others. Hence all our choices are, on that
accounting, determined or necessary. Nonetheless, most of us have a very keen
sense that what we choose, we choose voluntarily; we could have chosen
otherwise than we did choose. In short, it seems we have free will. But how is
it possible, or is it possible, that our choices might be causally determined
and free at the same time? This is one way of stating the basic problem of free
will and determinism.
In this example of freedom and determinism how can
we clarify the statement of the problem? According to the statement, for
everything that happens, there are some laws which made it necessary that
thing, and only that thing happened. But here we ask, what exactly is the sense
of the word necessary here? Or in another place, the statement reads, We have a
very distinct impression that what we choose, we choose voluntarily; we could
have chosen otherwise than how we did. But what is the strength of this phrase
'could have'? The idea appears to be that it is in some sense possible for us
to choose otherwise; but in what sense of ‘possible’ is it possible? An enquiry into the problem of freedom and
determinism, or any philosophical problem, can only benefit from getting very
clear about exactly what the problem is, and what the terms used to formulate
the problem signify.
Enunciate a solution: To enunciate a theory, or to
give a definition or analysis, which constitutes an attempt to solve a
philosophical problem is another essential part of philosophical method. In
just a sentence or two a philosophical theory by itself can be stated quite
briefly very often all the surrounding philosophical text is offered by way of
hedging, explanation, and argument. Here as an example let us take a
philosophical theory which has to answer the question what actions are right?
For this the answer is given by John Stuart Mill, an English philosopher, as
the creed which accepts as the foundation of morals utility, or the greatest
happiness principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to
promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.
Consequently, according to Stuart Mill, the rightness or wrongness of actions
depends on their consequences; if they tend to cause happiness they are morally
right, and if they tend to cause unhappiness they are morally wrong. Whether we
accept the answer or not is a different question but it does answer the
question, what actions are right.
Justify the solution: Another important part of philosophical
method is philosophical justifications, or arguments. An argument is a set of
statements, one of which, the conclusion, it is said or implied, follows from
the others which is called the premises. We might think of arguments as bundles
of reasons which are logically interconnected statements. The reasons are the
premises, the claim they support is the conclusion; together they make an
argument. Normally philosophers are very good in giving arguments. They are
constantly demanding and offering arguments for different claims they make. The
reason for this is that it is only a good argument, a clear, organized, and
sound statement of reasons to believe something that will ultimately cure us of
the original doubts that motivated us to take up philosophy. Let us illustrate
this point with an example of an argument. Say Susan has some doubts about
religious matters, and she asks the question: Does God really exist? Susan’s
answer is, we will say, yes. How might Susan argue for her answer? Here is a very
common, popular argument, called the argument from design.
The universe is made up of a huge variety of things,
inanimate and living, natural and artificial from the hills and the oceans, to
the houses and ships on them, from the stars and planets, to the cities and
highways. All of this huge variety of things is, as scientists well know,
operating in a splendid order or harmony, much like a very complicated machine,
only much more complicated and well-planned than anything that we humans have
ever invented. Like a machine, this order or harmony could not have just sprung
into existence all on its own; like a machine, it must have had a designer.
Moreover, since the universe is so complicated and well-planned, this designer
must be incredibly intelligent; and since everything is so well-made for the
habitation of humans, this designer must be very benevolent. And of course, as
the creator and planner of the entire universe, this designer must be extremely
powerful. So the universe must have had a designer which is incredibly
intelligent, very benevolent, and extremely powerful; and this designer is what
we call God. Therefore, God exists.
This argument is called the teleological argument
which is studied the philosophy of religion. It offers a series of interconnected
reasons to believe that there does exist the sort of entity that in various
religions is called God. This sort of argument is just exactly what
philosophers want from each other. To deserve our consideration, the argument
does not have to be perfect. It might have some problems. In fact, it might be
a very bad argument. But on the face of it, there should be something rather
persuasive about it. That gives us something to analyse and learn.
Philosophical criticism: Philosophical criticism is
common in the work of philosophers. It is this philosophical criticism that
makes much philosophizing a social endeavour and so on. We offer definitions
and explanations in solution to problems; we argue for those solutions; and
then other people come along and, often, demolish those solutions, throw us
into doubt again, and force us to come up with better solutions. This exchange
and resulting revision of views is called dialectic. Dialectic is simply
philosophical conversation amongst people who do not always agree with each
other about everything. These are the five steps that a philosophical method
involves in its journey towards finding the truth. Having studied the
philosophical method let us move on to know about scientific method.
4.4 SCIENTIFIC METHOD
The scientific method is the only scientific way
accepted to back up a theory or idea.
This is the method on which all research projects should be based. The Scientific Method is used by researchers
to support or disprove a theory. People attempt to understand something
sufficiently to reproduce an event and/or accurately predict an event with the
scientific method.
The Scientific Method has Four Steps
• Observation
and description of a phenomenon or group of phenomena.
• Formulation
of a hypothesis to explain the phenomena.
• Use
of the hypothesis to predict the existence of other phenomena, or to predict
quantitatively the results of new observations.
• Performance
of experimental tests of the predictions by several independent experimenters
and properly performed experiments.
Iterations, recursions, interleavings, and orderings
are the scientific method's essential elements of the following four steps.
Iteration is the repetition of a process. It is a repetition in a specific form
of repetition with a mutable state and recursion is a particular way of
specifying or constructing a class of objects with the help of a reference to
other objects of the class: a recursive definition defines objects in terms of
the already defined objects of the class. Interleaving is a way to arrange data
in a non-contiguous way to increase performance. Orderings formalizes the
intuitive concept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of
a set.
Characterization: The scientific method depends upon
a careful characterization of the subject of the investigation. Here the
subject may also be called the problem or the unknown. Observation demands
careful measurement and the use of operational definitions of relevant
concepts. Formally, these terms have exact meanings which do not necessarily
correspond with their natural language usage. For example, mass and weight are
quite distinct concepts. New theories may also arise upon realizing that
certain terms had not previously been clearly defined. For example, Albert
Einstein's first paper on relativity begins by defining simultaneity and the
means for determining length. These ideas were skipped over by Newton with,
"I do not define time, space, place and motion, as being well known to all."
Einstein's paper then demonstrates that these widely accepted ideas were
invalid.
Hypothesis: A hypothesis is a suggested explanation
of a phenomenon, or alternately a reasoned proposal suggesting a possible
correlation between or among a set of phenomena. A hypothesis includes a
suggested explanation of the subject. It will generally provide a causal
explanation or propose some correlation. Observations have the general form of
existential statements, stating that some particular instance of the phenomenon
being studied has some characteristic. Causal explanations have the general
form of universal statements, stating that every instance of the phenomenon has
a particular characteristic. It is not deductively valid to infer a universal
statement from any series of particular observations. This is the problem of
induction. Scientists use whatever they can, their own creativity, ideas from
other fields, induction, systematic guessing, etc to imagine possible
explanations for a phenomenon under study. There are no definitive guidelines
for the production of new hypotheses. The history of science is filled with
stories of scientists claiming a "flash of inspiration", or a hunch,
which then motivated them to look for evidence to support or refute their idea.
Michael Polanyi made such creativity the centerpiece of his discussion of
methodology. The present-day system of methods in science is as diversified as
science itself. We talk, for example, of experimental method, the method of
processing empirical data, the method of building scientific theories and their
verification, the method of expounding scientific results, i.e., the
classification of methods based on the classification of stages of research
activity. We have dealt with scientific and philosophical methods with this
background let us move on to study the relation between scientific and
philosophical methods.
Check Your Progress II
4.5. THE RELATION
Can philosophy develop by itself, without the
support of science? Can science ‘work’ without philosophy? Some people think
that the sciences can stand apart from philosophy, that the scientist should
actually avoid philosophising, the latter often being understood as groundless
and generally vague theorising. If the term philosophy is given such a poor
interpretation, then of course anyone would agree with the warning ‘Physics,
beware of metaphysics’ But no such warning applies to philosophy in the higher
sense of the term. The specific sciences cannot and should not break their
connections with true philosophy.
We can find the direct relation of scientific and
philosophical methods by analysing the steps. Scientific method starts wish
observation and description where in observation plays a vital role. It is this
observation paves way to the sense of wonder and doubt which is the first step
in the philosophical method. The second method in the scientific method is
formulation of hypothesis which includes a suggested explanation of the subject
which helps one to formulate questions and problems which is the second step in
the philosophical method. Use of the hypothesis to predict the existence of
other phenomena, or to predict quantitatively the results of new observations
is the third step in the scientific method. This prediction of quantitatively
the results of new observations makes one to enunciate a solution in a problem
which is the third step in the philosophical method. The fourth step in the
scientific method is the performance of experimental tests of the predictions
by several independent experimenters and properly performed experiments. This
performance of repeated experimental tests in scientific method helps one to
justify the solution that is enunciated in the third step of the philosophical
method. Further it leads one to criticize the solution dialectically which is
called philosophical criticism, the final step in the philosophical method.
This evidently shows how scientific method and philosophical method helps one
to arrive at a conclusion and how they complement each other in finding the
truth.
In ancient times, as we have seen, nearly every
notable scientist was at the same time a philosopher and every philosopher was
to some extent a scientist. Which means both scientists and philosophers have
used both the methods in their journey towards finding the truth. The
connection between scientific methods and philosophical methods has endured for
thousands of years. In present-day conditions it has not only been preserved
but is also growing substantially stronger. The common ground of a substantial part
of the content of science, its facts and laws has always related it to
philosophy, particularly in the field of the theory of knowledge, and today
this common ground links it with the problems of the moral and social aspects
of scientific discoveries and technical inventions.
Philosophy deals with experience rather than
speculations. It deals with the same materials as science and its methods even
shade into the method of science. The same relation holds with the reference
with the use of hypothesis in thinking and in scientific investigation.
Philosophers at some time regarded it as their function to examine the
unrecognised hypotheses or assumptions which underlie the procedure of
scientific workers. A slightly different function which is regarded as a special
problem of philosophy is the setting up of hypotheses. It has been pointed out
that fruitful hypotheses are sometimes suggested by speculative thinkers before
they have been thought of, much less tested, by scientists.
The scientific method has drawn many parallels with
the philosophy of modern empiricism and its search for meaningful statements.
The scientific method seems to be a constantly moving entity that has evolved
from the first conscious thought to the present day. It appears to be changing
all the time based not only on the views of individual scientists and
philosophers, but also on the social situations and collective intelligence of
the times, which interestingly has been affected by the method itself.
Philosophy cannot, for example, give physics
specific methods for studying quantum mechanics. But it is concerned with the
general approach to discovery of truth in physics. It deals not with the
‘tactics’ of the research process, but with the strategy in the battle for
truth. Philosophical methods work in science not directly but mediated by other
more specific methods. For example, the principle of historicism as a universal
method evolved by philosophy has in biology taken the form of evolution theory,
the methodological basis of the modern biological disciplines, and in astronomy
this same principle has generated a whole set of cosmogonic hypotheses.
In science, methodology often decides the fate of a
research project. Different approaches may lead to opposite conclusions being
drawn from one and the same factual material. Describing the role of correct
method in scientific cognition, philosophers have compared it to a torch
illuminating the road for the traveller in darkness. Even a lame man who
chooses the right road will arrive ahead of the aimless wanderer. It goes
without saying that method in itself cannot guarantee success in research. Not
only a good method but skills in applying it are required. Thus the connection
between philosophical methods and scientific methods is mutual and
characterised by their ever deepening interaction which is an ongoing process.
Now we are clear about the relation between scientific and philosophical
methods. This knowledge will help us to understand the importance of scientific
and philosophical methods in the forth coming section.
4.6. THE IMPORTANCE OF PHILOSOPHICAL AND
SCIENTIFIC METHODS
Philosophy plays a tremendous integrating role in
scientific knowledge. The touchstone of the value of philosophy as a world-view
and methodology is the degree to which it is interconnected with life. This
interconnection may be both direct and indirect, through the whole system of
culture, through science, art, morality, religion, law, and politics. As a
special form of social consciousness, constantly interacting with all its other
forms, philosophy is their general theoretical substantiation and
interpretation. In ancient times, as we have seen, nearly every notable
scientist was at the same time a philosopher and every philosopher was to some
extent a scientist. Which means both scientists and philosophers have used both
the methods in their journey towards finding the truth. The connection between
science and philosophy has endured for thousands of years. Science and
philosophy have always learned from each other. Philosophy tirelessly draws
from scientific discoveries fresh strength, material for broad generalisations,
while to the sciences it imparts the world-view and methodological impulses of
its universal principles. Many general guiding ideas that lie at the foundation
of modern science were first enunciated by the perceptive force of
philosophical thought.
Any scientist knows in his/her heart that his/her
creative activity is closely linked with philosophy and that without serious
knowledge of philosophical culture the results of that activity cannot become
theoretically effective. All the outstanding theoreticians have themselves been
guided by philosophical thought and tried to inspire their pupils with its
beneficent influence in order to make them specialists capable of
comprehensively and critically analyzing all the principles and systems known
to science, discovering their internal contradictions and overcoming them by
means of new concepts.
Truly scientific thought is philosophical to the
core, just as truly philosophical thought is profoundly scientific, rooted in
the sum-total of scientific achievements. Philosophical training gives the
scientist a breadth and penetration, a wider scope in posing and resolving
problems. Philosophy may be called the ‘science of sciences’ probably in the
sense that it is, in effect, the self-awareness of the sciences and the source
from which all the sciences draw their world-view and methodological
principles, which in the course of centuries have been honed down into concise
forms. As a whole, philosophy and the sciences are equal partners assisting
creative thought in its explorations to attain generalizing truth. The
philosophical approach enables us to overcome the one-sidedness in research
which has a negative effect in modern highly specialised scientific work. It is
philosophy that safeguards the unity and interconnection of all aspects of
knowledge of the vast and diversified world whose substance is matter.
The scientific knowledge in various fields develops,
the stronger is the tendency to study the logical system by which we obtain
knowledge, the nature of theory and how it is constructed, to analyse the
empirical and theoretical levels of cognition, the initial concepts of science
and methods of arriving at the truth. In short, the sciences show an increasing
desire to know themselves, the mind is becoming more and more reflective.
Self-knowledge is the present-day trend. This trend towards self-knowledge, of
which much is said both by scientists and philosophers, is bound to show itself
and should show itself in the relationship between philosophical methods and
scientific methods. At this juncture I would say philosophical methods and the
scientific methods are two sides of a same coin. They both complement each
other and enhance our day-to-day life situation. By this time we must have a
panoramic view of philosophical methods and scientific methods and its relation
and how they help us in our present life.
Check Your Progress III
4.7 LET US SUM UP
Having a good introduction about the philosophical
and scientific methods we have studied the definitions of philosophical and
scientific methods and this paved the way to venture into what is philosophical
method where in we studied the methodology process which is a systematic process of doubting or being skeptical about
the truth of one's beliefs. This methodology process comprises of Doubt and the
sense of wonder, Formulate questions and problems, Enunciate a solution, justify
the solution and Philosophical criticism. After dealing with the methodology
process we moved on to scientific methods where in we studied the four steps of
scientific methodology and the four elements that are involved in that method.
These two sections presented us what is philosophical method and scientific
method. Now the work is to see the relation and that is what we have done in
the next section which tells us the relation between philosophical and
scientific methods and the connection between philosophical methods and
scientific methods is mutual and characterised by their ever deepening
interaction which is an ongoing process. This understanding moved us to
investigate the importance of scientific and philosophical methods which tells
us both methods are important in our everyday life and help us to have a clear
self-knowledge. Thus we have finished the unit with a note that philosophical
methods and the scientific methods are two sides of a same coin. They both
complement each other and enhance our day-to-day life situation.
4.8 KEY WORDS
Argument: an argument is a set of statements, one of
which, the conclusion, it is said or implied, follows from the others which is
called the premises.
Dialectic: Dialectic is simply philosophical
conversation amongst people who do not always agree with each other about
everything.
Hypothesis: Hypothesis is a suggested explanation of
a phenomenon, or alternately a reasoned proposal suggesting a possible
correlation between or among a set of phenomena.
Theory: A theory is an explanation of a set of
related observations or events based upon proven hypotheses and verified
multiple times by detached groups of researchers.
Block 2 Early
Methods in Philosophy
UNIT I DIALECTICAL METHOD
Contents
1.0 Objectives
1.1
Introduction and a Brief Survey of the Method
1.2
Types of Dialectics
1.3 Dialectics
in Classical Philosophy
1.4 Dialectics
in Modern Philosophy
1.5 Critique
of Dialectical Method
1.6 Let
Us Sum Up
1.7 Key
Words
1.8 References
and Further Readings
1.0 OBJECTIVES
Objective of this Unit is to provide a comprehensive
understanding of the Dialectical Method (also known as Dialectics and
Dialectic), which is one of the most influential philosophical ideas in the
history of mankind. The Unit attempts to demystify the seemingly complex idea
of Dialectics by providing a lucid account of it as well as the use of the
method in different ages in history. The
Unit discusses the methods of Dialectics in important classical and modern
philosophers - Heraclitus, Gautama Buddha, Socrates, Aristotle, Hegel, Karl
Marx, Friedrich Engels and the applications of these methods. In addition, an
attempt is made to discuss the intellectual and historical impact created by
the application of Dialectics and Dialectical Method in order to keep students
informed about the power of the idea of Dialectic in particular and
philosophical ideas in general. It would be difficult to appreciate the power
of ideas in Philosophy without being aware of their real-time historical
implications. By the time of completion of this Unit, you should have a fair
idea of , forms of dialectics, major philosophers of dialectics, important
variants of dialectical method, and impact of dialectical thought.
1.1 INTRODUCTION AND A BRIEF SURVEY OF THE
METHOD
The term Dialectic is derived from the Greek terms
‘dia’ and ‘logos’ which mean dialogue or a conversation between two persons.
Dialectics can be traced back to pre-Socratic philosophy and has been used by
different philosophers in different eras of philosophy with different meanings.
As a result, the term Dialectics doesn’t have a single meaning or connotation.
This is the first important thing that should be taken note of as to the
understanding of dialectical method. The point becomes more obvious in the
following brief survey of various thinkers of Dialectics. The initial strands
of dialectics were associated with the ancient Greek philosopher Plato. Plato
first used the term for the art of discussion, in which participants try to
arrive at truth by exchanging logical arguments. His work Republic provides a
wonderful demonstration of this discussion method.
Aristotle considered Dialectics as a method of
examining the commonly held beliefs by the people. (Aristotle, Topics X)
According to Aristotle, Zeno of Elea, an ancient Greek philosopher was the
founder of dialectical thought. Zeno produced quite a lot of paradoxes to prove
motion is impossible. For example, he argued that an arrow shot from the bow
doesn’t move because at a given point in time, it would be in rest at some
space. Zeno examined the popular beliefs and refuted them based on his logic,
hence, according to Aristotle, he was the founder of dialectical thought. Here,
Dialectics was meant to deal with the art of argument or discussion.
Apart from these Greek philosophers, German idealist
thinkers Kant, Fichte, Schilling and Hegel made use of this method,
particularly Hegel. Kant in his Critique of Pure Reason, criticizing
speculative metaphysics said that it is not possible for human reason to grasp
things such as God, which do not fall under phenomena, which are appearances
and can be grasped by human intellect. He distinguished phenomena from noumena,
which consists of things-in-themselves and beyond the grasp of human intellect.
Showing the futility of noumenal arguments such as the World has a beginning in
time and is limited in space, Kant puts forth an equally forceful counter
argument like - the world has no beginning and no limitations in space, it is
infinite in time and space; and no argument can be proved at the end. Kant
called the first argument as Thesis and the second argument Anti-thesis, where
the latter proves the futility of the former. He termed this mode of criticism
as ‘Transcendental Dialectic’. Here Dialectic is a method of refutation.
Fichte, in his theory of consciousness, held that
evolution of ego, which is the only reality and source of self-consciousness,
takes place in three moments. They are (1) the ego, (2) the non-ego and (3)
setting both of them in opposition. He calls the first, the thesis, the second
antithesis and the third synthesis. While the ego is the principle of
knowledge, the non-ego, is equally independent of the ego and unlimited and a
negation of the former. The antithesis is assertion of a non-ego in opposition to
the ego. The synthesis is the determination of the first two through one
another, in such a way that the ego and the non-ego mutually limit each other.
Here for the first time, the dialectics got the triadic method and entered into
a speculative plane.
Schelling has attempted to construct nature or the
world a priori. His main aim was to reason out the necessary stages in the
evolution of nature where he found a dialectical process working through the
world. He has comprehended the two opposing activities viz., thesis, and
antithesis, which get united in a synthesis. He called this process the law of
triplicity, wherein the thesis is action, antithesis is reaction and synthesis
is the harmony between the two. Schelling applies the triadic dialectic to every
phase of organic and inorganic realms, to individual and social life, to
history science and art. Thus it is evident that Schelling regarded nature as a
dynamic evolutionary process of reason moving towards the self-conscious reason
of man. He has equated the necessary forms of thought with the necessary forms
of being.
The next major thinker in this series is Hegel.
Modeled on Schelling’s philosophy, presenting his grand philosophical system of
the world, Hegel attempts to explain the progress of history through the march
of the Absolute or Spirit. According to Hegel, the Spirit realizes itself in
the movement of history. At first, the Spirit was a pure idea. The very
affirmation of the Spirit faces its negation i.e. the non-Spirit. The being of
Spirit negated by non-being of Spirit doesn’t result in nothingness but in
becoming, the physical manifestation of the Spirit as the World. In Hegel,
dialectical theory entered into a speculative explanation of the Nature.
Bringing the Hegelian dialectics down from
speculative plane to reality, Karl Marx applied them in history and showed how
the human societies were always in a state of change due to clashing interests
of different economic classes. Marx’s economic interpretation of history
postulates that society had progressed from one mode of production to another
due to the struggle between the classes. In Marxian theory, Dialectics explain
different contradictions in the human societies and a conflictual movement of
them would lead to further progress.
Thus, the term Dialectics is used differently in
different epochs of philosophy. However, in the history of philosophy, two
fundamental tendencies – Dialectics as a theory of knowledge that explains
natural/social phenomena and Dialectics as a method of discourse – were
identified as the major types of Dialectics. However, often, at least in
popular writings, Dialectics is being identified with either of these
varieties, particularly with the methods developed by Plato or Hegel.
1.2 TYPES OF DIALECTICS
According to the first type, Dialectics is theory of
knowledge or a method of understanding that explains any given
phenomenon/process/object as a unity of opposites. This variant can be called
as Phenomenal Dialectics, phenomenal in the sense that - of, relating to, or
constituting phenomena or a phenomenon. The second one explains dialectics as a
method of logical discourse which tries to derive truth and this variant can be
called as Discourse Dialectics, discourse in the sense that a formal, lengthy discussion
of a subject, either written or spoken.
Phenomenal Dialectics: According to Phenomenal
Dialectics, any given phenomenon / object/process would always be in a state of
motion and it is a unity of opposites. And the development or change of the phenomenon/object/process
essentially happens through a constant and often conflictual movement of the
two latent opposites.
The variant of Dialectics owes its beginning to
Heraclitus, a great natural philosopher from ancient Greece. He explained that
all the objects in nature are always in a state of flux and existence of those
objects are possible due to tension between the opposites and unity of
them. His famous quote, “You cannot step
twice into the same river, for other waters and yet others go ever flowing on”
(William Harris, Heraclitus - The Complete Fragments, 20) indicates not just the ever-changing nature
of the river but all the phenomena of the Nature. He said, "Everything is
and is not, for everything is in flux, is constantly changing, constantly
coming into being and passing away". (Rob Swell, Introduction to The ABC
of Materialist Dialectics) Emphasizing the conflictual nature - i.e. unity of
opposites - of the aspects of objects and process, he stated that, “It should
be understood that war is the common condition, that strife is justice, and
that all things come to pass through the compulsion of strife.” (William
Harris, Heraclitus - The Complete Fragments, 26)
Friedrich Engels, cofounder of communism along with
Karl Marx, wonderfully puts it as “Dialectics is nothing more than the science
of the general laws of motion and development of nature, human society and
thought.” (Engels, Anti- Dühring). He described Dialectics as "The great
basic thought that the world is not to be comprehended as a complex of ready
made things, but as a complex of processes, in which things apparently stable,
no less than their mental images in our heads, concepts go through an
uninterrupted change of coming into being and passing away." (Engels,
Anti-Dühring)
For example, Karl Marx, using the Dialectical
Method, theorised that human history was
nothing but a chronicle of constant struggle between the divided economic
interests of two classes. Analyzing his contemporary times, he opined that
capitalism had emerged as the order of the day by defeating feudalism. However,
Marx said, its demise was inevitable as it was creating its potential opponent
i.e. working class. The working class would defeat capitalism and progress to
the next level in the history i.e. to socialism. In Marxian theory of history,
one can see constant change and continuous or conflictual movement of the
opposites, two defining traits of phenomenal dialectics. Heraclitus, Gautama
Buddha, Hegel, Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels are major thinkers who developed
the phenomenal dialectic method.
Discourse
Dialectics
Discourse Dialectics is rooted in the philosophy of
Plato, who defined the method and used it extensively in his writings. Indeed
the word ‘Dialectic’ was first used by Heraclitus who developed Dialectics as a
method of argument for arriving at the truth by the exchange of logical
arguments. Platonic Dialectic is based on a dialogue between two or more people
who may hold differing views, yet wish to pursue truth by seeking agreement with
one another. Two major discourse dialecticians Plato and Aristotle are
discussed in this Unit.
1.3 DIALECTICS IN CLASSICAL PHILOSOPHY
In this section, we shall discuss Phenomenal
Dialectics of Heraclitus and Gautama Buddha and Discourse Dialectics of Plato
and Aristotle. Heraclitus was a fascinating Greek natural philosopher who
predicted quite a few of scientific discoveries made in modern days such as the
Law of Conservation of Energy and Law of Conservation of Matter. Heraclitus was
deeply concerned about the knowledge levels of his fellow human beings and went
on to explain Nature in his cryptic propositions. According to Hegel,
Heraclitus was the founder of Dialectic method. His method of Dialectics can be
explained by way of two theories - theory of flux and theory of unity of
opposites. He famously said – one cannot
step into the same river twice and the one exists and does not exist. According
to Heraclitus, everything is and is not; everything is in flux, is constantly
changing and constantly coming into being and passing away. By saying this, he
meant that the river exists since it is there and it is not there since there
is nothing but the flowing waters; the human being who steps into the river
also exists since he is and he doesn’t exist since he undergoes change every
second. These notions explain how change
is the only permanent law of nature.
Theory of Unity
of Opposites
Heraclitus maintained that all the phenomena of
Nature were possible due to the conflict and unity between the opposite
features/aspects that are latent in those phenomena. When he said, “You cannot
step twice into the same river, for other waters and yet others go ever flowing
on.” The ‘same river’ and ‘other waters’ are exact opposites. It means, though
the waters are always changing, the river stays the same. Indeed, it must be
precisely because the waters are always changing that there is a river at all,
rather than lake or pond. The message is that river can stay the same over time
even though, or indeed because, the waters change. The point, then, is not that
everything is changing, but that the fact that some things change makes
possible the continued existence of other things. Perhaps more generally, the
change in elements or constituents supports the constancy of higher-level
structures.
Another insight of Heraclitus, “It throws apart and
then brings together again; it advances and retires.” (William Harris,
Heraclitus - The Complete Fragments, 31) explains elements coming together in a
combinatory process, and then dissociating in Nature. This notion is quite
important in understanding the phenomena of Nature in its being, becoming and
diminution stages. These stages are exclusive and identical at the same time.
Thus unity of the opposite aspects of the same object/process/phenomenon makes
the change/development possible. Heraclitus’ theories of flux and unity of
opposites, formed the basis for what was later called as Dialectics, had
iconoclastic effect in ancient Greek natural philosophy. He openly opposed the
permanence of soul and dogmatic practices of erstwhile religion, thus created
foundations for materialism in Western thought. Heraclitus’ thought had direct
influence on Hegel, who further influenced Karl Marx, which is a clear
demonstration of his powerful legacy.
Dialectic Method
of Buddha
Gautama Buddha, a light dawn on the Indian
subcontinent around 563 B.C., infused peace into a disheartened nation with his
profound teachings. He condemned all the dogma associated with erstwhile
orthodox Vedic religion. His doctrine of momentariness or Ksanika Vada, which
was part of his rational teachings, can be considered as Buddhist theory of
Phenomenal Dialectic. With this doctrine, Buddha ruled out the eternality of
the soul and all the logics that were related to the permanency in the Vedic
religion. Buddha emphatically said all the things that have origination must
perish and the world is a becoming, it is Bhavarup. Everything in this world is
merely a conglomeration of perishable qualities. Everything is momentary. This
world is determined by the principle of dependent origination and animals,
Gods, plants, things, bodies, forms, substances…all are perishable. Everything
has a beginning, existence and extinction. This was the middle path posited by
Buddha, a way between the views of absolute existence and absolute nihilism.
This teaching of Buddha had helped the restoration of rational thinking in the
erstwhile dispirited nation. Buddha and
Heraclitus, both of them didn’t use the term Dialectics. However, this doesn’t
stop their theories to be qualified as foundations of dialectical method in the
East and the West respectively.
Dialectics of
Plato
The term has been connected with Plato in the
history of philosophy as a method of discussion. Before going into the details
of Plato’s Dialectic Method, it is important to know how the concept of natural
philosophy, during the time of Heraclitus, had transformed into a method of
discussion. August Thalheimer, a German
Marxist thinker, theorised that development of a slave labour system had
dragged the Greek city state into wars for a perennial supply of slaves, hindered
technical progress and also gave rise to parasitic behaviour among its free
citizens. (August Thalheimer, Introduction to Dialectical Materialism - The
Marxist World-View, Greek Idealism) As a result, scientific growth had stopped
and questions of natural philosophy had lost relevance, instead questions
related to human conduct gained prominence.
Plato developed Dialectic Method as an art of
discussion, through which participants try to arrive at truth, by exchange of
logical arguments. British philosopher Simon Blackburn defined Plato’s
Dialectic Method as “The process of eliciting the truth by means of questions
aimed at opening out what is already implicitly known, or at exposing the
contradictions and muddles of an opponent’s position” (Simon Blackburn, Plato’s
Republic – A Biography, p. 104). Plato
had popularized this method by making extensive use of this method in his
works. The dialectic dialogue is also known as Socratic Method or Socratic
Irony, in which Socrates attempts to examine someone's beliefs and argues by
cross-examining his opponent’s claims and premises in order to point out
inconsistency among them in order to take them nearer to the truth.
According to Ryan Patrick Canney, Plato’s
dialectical method requires the following: 1) Participation and the appearance
of equal status among those involved, 2) Starting the dialogue with commonly
held views and ideas, 3) Dialogue that leads to critical reflection amongst the
participants, and 4) Connection of ideas brought up in discussion. (Ryan
Patrick Canney, The Dialectic Today: Critically Interrogating the Socratic
Method for Contemporary Use). Plato’s
method of discussion is different from debate, in which two people try to
disprove each other and also rhetoric, which aims at winning over others in an
argument by mastering argumentation techniques but not the facts about the
subject matter. In his Gorgias, Socrates gets Gorgias, a rhetorician, to agree
that a rhetorician is actually more convincing in front of an ignorant audience
than an expert, because mastery of the tools of persuasion gives a man more
convincingness than knowledge of subject matter. Gorgias concedes this
criticism and asserts that it is an advantage of rhetoric that a man can be
considered above specialists without having to learn anything of substance.
Socrates calls rhetoric a form of flattery and compares it to pastry baking and
cosmetic beautification. He says that rhetoric is to politics what pastry
baking is to medicine, and what cosmetics are to gymnastics. All of these
activities are aimed at surface adornment, an imitation of what is really good.
(Plato, Gorgias) Plato had provided solid foundations for quite a lot of
philosophical ideas with his irrefutable arguments that formed the basis for
Western philosophy. Indeed, he had outlined the important questions that formed
the subject matter for philosophers for the next 1500 years.
Dialectical Method of Aristotle
Aristotle worked on Dialectics at length in his
Topics. He divided the possible kinds of reasonings in an argument or
discussion into four kinds, of which dialectical proposition is the second one:
Demonstrations, which are based on premises that are primary and true:
Dialectical propositions, which have commonly held opinions as their premises;
Contentious, which have premises those seem to be common held, but are really
not; Mis-reasonings, which are based on the premises that are neither true nor
primary. He further defined dialectical proposition as some thing that examines
the endoxos i.e. commonly held beliefs. However, every proposition and every
problem can not be set down as dialectical. The endoxos must not be the view
which no one holds or which is obvious to everyone. If nobody holds a
particular view, any reasoning would not be possible and if it is obvious to
everyone, then there is no place for doubt. The dialectical propositions are a
kind of assertion and not demonstrations.
Given the picture of dialectical proposition, the
dialectical art comprises of two elements: a method for discovering premises
from which a given conclusion follows, a method for determining which premises
a given participator will be likely to concede.
A dialectical problem is a subject of inquiry that contributes either to
choice and avoidance, or to truth and knowledge, and that either by itself or
in tandem with some other fact helps in the solution of some other such
problem. Dialectical reasoning, according to Aristotle, is useful in a).
intellectual training, b). casual encounters and c). the philosophical
sciences. He said, “It (dialectical reasoning) is useful as training is obvious
on the face of it. The possession of a plan of inquiry will enable us more
easily to argue about the subject proposed. For purposes of casual encounters,
it is useful because when we have counted the opinions held by most people, we
shall meet them on the ground not of other people's convictions but of their
own, while we shift the ground of any argument that they appear to us to state
unsoundly.” (Aristotle, Topics, X)
“For the study of the philosophical sciences it is
useful, because the ability to raise searching difficulties on both sides of a
subject will make us detect more easily the truth and error about the several
points that arise. It has a further use in relation to the ultimate bases of
the principles used in the several sciences. For it is impossible to discuss
them at all from the principles proper to the particular science in hand,
seeing that the principles are the prius of everything else: it is through the
opinions generally held on the particular points that these have to be
discussed, and this task belongs properly, or most appropriately, to dialectic:
for dialectic is a process of criticism wherein lies the path to the principles
of all inquiries.” (Ibid.) Aristotle’s analysis of Dialectics, as part of his
exploration of Logic, provided a beginning for analytical examination of the
method.
1.4 DIALECTICS IN MODERN PHILOSOPHY
Hegelian Dialectics
After Greek philosophers, it was German idealist
thinkers who worked on Dialectic method in an apperceptive fashion. While Kant
used dialectics as a principle of self-contradiction, Fichte made use of it to
explain his evolution of self-consciousness and for the first time used the
thesis-antithesis-synthesis triode. Schelling fully developed dialectics as a
method that explains the phenomenon of nature and utilised the triadic method.
Based on Schelling, it was Hegel who worked out a complete system of the world
through speculative reasoning. He wanted to have the fullest knowledge of past,
present and future through this system. Hegel’s system has many similarities
with that of Adi Sankara, whose doctrine of Brahman also captures the eternal
knowledge.
Hegel argues
that "what is rational is real and what is real is rational." This
must be understood in terms of Hegel's further claim that the Absolute must
ultimately be regarded as pure Thought, or Spirit, or Mind, in the process of
self-development. According to Hegel’s system, beginning of history happens
with the beginning of the primitive Spirit or Absolute Being. This Spirit was
so poor and simple that when it had faced its anti-thesis i.e. nothingness and
in a perennial and conflictual movement, the synthesis is produced i.e.
Becoming. In an unlimited series of phenomena, the Being constructs itself
continuously and becomes more conscious about itself. The perennial movement
between the opposites i.e. the Being and non-Being make self-construction and
self-revelation possible. This reality, or the total developmental process of
everything that is, he referred to as Absolute Spirit. According to Hegel, the
task of philosophy is to chart the development of Absolute Spirit. This
involves (1) making clear the internal rational structure of the Absolute; (2)
demonstrating the manner in which the Absolute manifests itself in nature and
human history; and (3) explicating the teleological nature of the Absolute,
that is, showing the end or purpose toward which the Absolute is directed.
Being, in other words, is characterized in its development by three stages:
being (thesis), non-being (antithesis), becoming (synthesis). It is in this
that Hegel's system of triads consists. This higher entity, at the same time it
becomes being, is lacerated, so to speak, by its opposite (i.e., by non-being),
and tends to affirm itself in a still higher entity, and so on ad infinitum.
This activity of building and of tearing itself apart, with the intention of
rebuilding itself ad infinitum, is the life of Being.
Another important feature of the primordial Being is
rationality. It was essentially a perfect, rational thought that confirms the
development of Being in the dialectic process that confirms the series of
phenomena. This thesis of the World as nothing but ‘Becoming’ helped Hegel to
challenge the Aristotlian logic. According to Aristotle, the principle of
identity could be formulated because the concept of being is always the same --
A is equal to A, and A cannot be its negation (non-A) at the same time and in
the same respect. For Hegel, this logic is faulty because it misinterprets
reality. For him reality is never identical with itself, but at every moment
changes, passing from what it is to what it is not. Contradiction, therefore,
is the life of concrete being. The progress of history happened through a
logical process of developing in accordance with the law of coincidence of
opposites. This process depends upon a fundamental triad: Idea (Logos), Nature,
Spirit. This triad indicates a logical rather than a chronological succession,
for the entire process is actuated within the primordial Spirit, in which all
is immanent.
Idea or Logos is the system of the pure concept
which lay at the foundation of all reality. Nature is the objectivation of the
Idea. It is the Idea's becoming other than itself, or its self-extension in
time and space. But it is the Universal Spirit which establishes itself in the
series of phenomena extended in space and time, with the purpose of developing
itself and of gaining consciousness of self. Nature reaches the height of
perfection in the human organism, and the human organism attains the peak of
perfection in individual consciousness or Subjective Spirit. With the
attainment of this supreme stage of perfection there begins the return of
nature to the Universal Spirit. Indeed, the Subjective Spirit is the first
appearance of the Universal Spirit as rationality and freedom. But in the
narrow limits of individuality, the Subjective Spirit can never reach the
fullness of rationality and freedom, which is the consummation of the entire
process of the Spirit. To realize this ultimate end (the fullness of
rationality and freedom), the Subjective Spirit objectivates itself in many
super individual forms; i.e., it constructs the ethical world.
The first objectivation is the juridical order or
right, which guarantees freedom to all in a measure compatible with the freedom
of others. Right can regulate only external conduct. The spirit which aspires
to regulate the interior world also, objectivates itself in a higher form,
i.e., in morality. Morality concretizes itself:
1. In the family, in which the spirit reveals itself
as a union of souls;
2. In civil society, which is a larger and higher
community of souls; and, lastly,
3. In the state, the highest revelation that the
spirit gives to itself.
The Objective Spirit of the people manifests itself
in the State, which is the living God. The living God incarnates Himself now in
this, now in that nation, according as the nation realizes more perfectly than
any other the ideal of civilization. As the Spirit passes from one nation to
another, the chosen people by the Spirit conquers and dominates the others.
Although the state is the highest objectivation and manifestation of the
Spirit,
Hegel places the Universal or Absolute Spirit over
the objective spirit. The Absolute Spirit – which expresses itself through art,
religion and philosophy -- fully actuates the consciousness of its divine
nature in a reckoning with itself. In art the Spirit apprehends its absolute
essence as an idea expressing a sensible object: the beautiful is an idea
sensibly concretized, in which the infinite is seen as finite. In religion, on
the other hand, there is the unity of the finite with the infinite. The
infinite is immanent in the finite, but in a sentimental, imaginative, mythical
form. The Hegelian concept, in which the state is the living God and
individuals but passing shadows, and in which, moreover, conflict and war are
affirmations of the vitality of the state, has been put to the test in the
German nation. Needless to say, Hegel's concept of reality is immanentist,
pantheistic and atheistic.
Dialectics in
Karl Marx
While Hegel talks of resolving contradictions
removed from Kant’s pursuit of objective truth, his understanding of dialectic
thought remained rooted in the notion of an ideal distinct from reality. Marx
in a significant departure from the idealistic dialectics of Hegel embedded the
Hegelian triad of affirmation, negation and the negation of negation in a more
discrete zone of the socially apparent and the materially manifest. The idea or
the concept for Marx was not something that existed beyond social realities, as
was Hegel’s wont, but was the direct result of the forces shaping the concepts
that underlay social reality. A more direct application of this idea translated
into the field of historical materialism, whereby history became a result
achieved through the resolution of the contradiction inherent in the hierarchy
of social and specifically class, i.e. economic divisions. So for Marx history
was a byproduct of the class struggle. The attempt of the proletariat, or the
economically marginalized, to correct the prevailing contradiction of their own
subordinated existence. This was a
direct application of the discourse of dialectics into the tangible or the
real. A thought process that did not make such a move into the realm of
pragmatic action would, for Marx, remain an empty ideology. Something that
would be philosophising shallowly, akin to mysticism or spirituality, rather
than a concrete imperative to action.
For Marx the demystification of Hegelian Dialectics
was predicated upon the principle that the world was “knowable,” the human mind
in effect stood at the apex of a rational order which interpreted the dynamism
of forces associated with social change and rendered that change with the
possibility of interpretation: “To Hegel, the life process of the human brain,
i.e. the process of thinking, which, under the name of ‘the idea,’ he even transforms into an independent
subject, is the demiurgos of the real world, and the real world is only the
external, phenomenal form of ‘the idea.’ With me, on the contrary, the ideal is
nothing else than the material world reflected by the human mind, and
translated into forms of thought.” (Capital, Volume 1, p.29).
This line of thought is central to Marx’s idea of
control that can be exercised over a knowable and material world. In such a world oppositions of power and
authority, divided amongst strata of society that have access to authority and
are denied it, are instrumental in initiating moves that would eventually
resolve social contradictions premised on class. To iterate an earlier
argument, it is such moves working towards a resolution of ideas of control
that create history. Anything that exists outside the purview of such a
material movement would not classify as history in Marx’s account.
The concept of the Being is an integral part of
Hegel’s speculation regarding the process of knowing. The being, which in other
words is the thesis, in trying to know and position itself also privileges the
non-being or absence or anti-thesis, eventually the union of such an opposition
results in a more absolutist version of ‘becoming’ where the spirit of the
discourse becomes the synthesis. But for Marx this version of dialectic thought
privileging speculation remained at the level of dangerous metaphysics,
dangerous because it made the individual in society impotent and incapable of
action. Marx replaced the notion of unity within Hegelian dialectics with the
idea of struggle. And to present it in a more reductive and perhaps vulgar
fashion the struggle of a class of people over another with the ultimate aim of
overthrowing one and gaining control over the means of production. It is at the height of an almost pre ordained
logic that Marx declares his methodology of Dialectics to be: “[A] scandal and
abomination to bourgeoisdom and its doctrinaire professors, because it includes
in its comprehension an affirmative recognition of the existing state of
things. At the same time also, the recognition of the negation of that state of
its inevitable breaking up; because it regards every historically developed
social form as in fluid movement, and therefore takes into account its
transient nature not less than its momentary existence; because it lets nothing
impose upon it, and is in its essence critical and revolutionary.”
(Capital)
Contradiction lies at the heart of the critique that
Marx offers, so also does Hegel, but for Hegel it is the route towards
understanding a transcendent notion of being and space of the real occupied by
the being. For Marx the contradiction is in a way pejorative and something that
needs to be reconciled keeping in mind the demands of a more equitable social
order. And it is to satisfy this demand that ‘the critical’ and the platform it
provides for conflict and struggle becomes significant.
Friedrich Engels
Engels and Marx occupy the same range of the
Dialectic spectrum. Engels determined three laws of dialectics from his reading
of Hegel’s Science of Logic. He
elaborated on these laws in his work Dialectics of Nature: The law of the unity
and conflict of opposites, The law of the passage of quantitative changes into
qualitative changes, The law of the negation of the negation
The law of unity and conflict emphasizes the idea of
struggle central to Marxian dialectics. In such a space the apparent unities of
coincidence, identity and equal action are transient and always subordinated to
the struggle embodied by the conflict of opposites. The transition of states in
the second law finds social resonance in the analysis of demographic changes
and the resultant changes in social structure. The third law highlights the
contradictory nature of a delimited being and the divisive tendencies innate to
the phenomenon that translate into our understanding of the being.
While Marx believed that Hegel’s dialectic was disrupted
by its idealism, and reversed Hegel’s idealistic dialectic from a material
position, Engels addressed Marx far more directly. Engels held that Marx’s
dialectic is “nothing more than the science of the general laws of motion and
development of nature, human society and thought,” where development of nature
and society is the foundation on which the development of thought rests. For
Engels all of nature itself was the summation of a continuing dialectical
process. In Anti-Duhring he contended
that a negation of negation is; “A very simple process which is taking place
everywhere and everyday, which any child can understand as soon as it is
stripped of the veil of mystery in which it was enveloped by the old idealist
philosophy.”
In effect Engels deviates from the far more direct
and brutal rationalization of conflict in Marx by tempering the nature of that
struggle in a more organic environment. For Engels the state of conflict was a
natural phenomenon prevalent in the universe, the upturning of social orders
also perhaps a consequence of the consistent impetus for change in the fabric
of nature and society. All Nature, from the smallest thing to the biggest, from
a grain of sand to the sun, from the protista to man, is in a constant state of
coming into being and going out of being, in a constant flux, in a ceaseless
state of movement and change. (Dialectics of Nature)
The building of such momentum manifested itself in
the hierarchical inversions highlighted by Marx but also in the words of Engels
created a natural state of expectancy that governed the change. In short while
the template of struggle is provided by Marx’s position, according to Engel’s
the change itself perhaps follows a natural pattern and in a way is
anticipated. Thus a doctrine of
development is encompassed by the idea of dialectics that is very different
from a conventional approach towards a general concept of development. A doctrine that talks of progression in terms
of the image of spirals rather than something compounded in a linear fashion.
Here progress is not incremental but abrupt, sudden
and in many ways apocalyptic. Engels firmly believed along with Marx that
qualitative changes that he spoke of in his writings were only possible through
such disruptions. What interested Engels’s the most was the process of such
instrumental change as evoked in his three conceptual laws/premises that he
arrived at after a careful consideration of Hegel’s idealistic dialectic. What is evident from the evaluation of such
concept based cognitive mapping of the ideational being is the negation of the
sacred. The emergent pattern then is a complete abjuring of unified terms such
as the final or the absolute. This is done for the simple reason that
totalizations such as the sacred would permit a social closure whereby the
essential contradiction of social divides gain a completely natural sanction,
and this is something that a materialistic dialectic espoused by Marx and
Engels absolutely seeks to avoid.
1.5 CRITIQUE OF DIALECTICAL METHOD
Many philosophers have offered critiques of
Dialectical Method. One of the general points made is that, in Dialectics,
harmony and unity are not emphasized; only tensions, paradoxes and
contradictions are highlighted. Critics of Hegel like Arthur Schopenhauer argue
that the selection of any antithesis, other than the logical negation of the
thesis, is subjective. Then, if the logical negation is used as the antithesis,
there is no rigorous way to derive a synthesis. In practice, when an antithesis
is selected to suit the user's subjective purpose, the resulting
"contradictions" are rhetorical, not logical, and the resulting
synthesis not rigorously defensible against a multitude of other possible
syntheses. Karl Popper unleashed a famous attack on Hegelian dialectics, in
which he held Hegel's thought was to some degree responsible for facilitating
the rise of fascism in Europe by encouraging and justifying irrationalism.
Some critics argue, while the dialectic in the
sphere of ideas can be defended, the concept as applied to the movement of
matter, in the manner of Marx, contradicts the ways of the natural world.
Nature is full of examples where growth and development occurs through the
dynamic movement of opposites, such as the positive and negative charges that
make up an atom, or male and female animals that mate to produce offspring.
However, in spite of the critics, it can be said that Dialectical Method
retains a central position in philosophy as an important research methodology
providing answers to some philosophical questions.
1.6 LET US SUM UP
In this Unit we tried to have a general
understanding of Dialectical Method tracing it from the Greek period to the
Modern times. We have rather elaborately seen the various nuances associated
with dialectical reasoning in its varied forms. The effort was to capture how
Dialectical Method of argument was central to both Western and Indian philosophical traditions, though in a brief
manner. The emphasis was to bring forth the uniqueness of Dialectics which is a
open, flexible, unassuming, critical, skeptical and holistic method taking into
consideration all aspects of reality through rational dialogue in the pursuit of truth in its earnestness.
1.7 KEY WORDS
Dialectic: Dialectic is a formal system of reasoning
that arrives at the truth by the exchange of logical arguments.
Negation: Negation involves the resolution of a
dialectical contradiction which transforms or resolves a thing, situation or
process in certain important respects, while also maintaining some similarity
or continuity with the previous thing, situation or process in other respects.
Example: Capitalism is the negation of feudalism.
Thesis, Anti-Thesis and Synthesis The thesis is an
intellectual proposition; Anti-thesis is a reaction to the proposition; the
synthesis solves the conflict between the thesis and antithesis by reconciling
their common truths, and forming a new proposition.
Quantitative Change and Qualitative Change: It's
part of the continuity-discontinuity issue. A quantitative change is a change
in numbers. A qualitative change is a change in quality
UNIT 2 RATIONAL
METHOD
Contents
2.0 Objectives
2.1 Introduction
2.2 Understanding
Rationalism
2.3 Rational
Method of Investigation
2.4. Descartes’
Rational Method
2.5 Leibniz’
Aim of Philosophy
2.6 Spinoza’
Aim of Philosophy
2.7 Let
us Sum up
2.8 Key
Words
2.9 Further
Readings and References
2.0 OBJECTIVES
In order to provide a solid foundation to philosophy
one need to adopt a solid and sound method. This unit explore the one of such
methods - “rational method” in the
discover of truth. This study on the rational method will enable a student …..
• To
see the immensity of the power of reasoning in philosophizing
• How
reason can lead us to clear and distinct truths
• Also
to value the mathematical tool in the demonstration of truth
2.1 INTRODUCTION
The renaissance began in 12th century in Italy and
flourished all over Europe by16th century made sweeping changes in all aspects
of life in the west. The awakening of the reflective spirit endowed with a
critical mind inspired by the values of the classical world almost redefined
the understandings of society, culture, religion, politics, art and literature.
Revolt against authority and tradition, intellectual and religious absolutism
and collectivism on the one hand and a demand for freedom in thought and action
on the other hand were the dominant trends of the period. Perhaps the most
important contribution of this period may be the recognition of the dignity, freedom
and importance of the human individual. In other words renaissance witnessed
the emergence of a new humanism freed from the strong hold of authority and
tradition.
The field of intellectual life was also affected by
this new trend. Reason took over the place of authority and tradition as the
standard or criterion of truth. Truth is now considered as something to be
acquired by impartial inquiry than what is decreed by religious authority and
revelation. The method of arriving at truth is now changed from contemplation
to empirical verification. Consequently an abiding faith in the power of human
reason became the fashion of the time. Knowledge then is esteemed for its
utility for the practical value too. Philosophy became more rationalistic in
the sense that reason became the highest criterion of knowledge leaving behind
the supernaturalism of scholasticism. Philosophy became more scientific than a
mere servant of Christian theology. Thus the modern thought was generally
classified as rationalistic and emperistic as they accept reason or experience
respectively as the source and norm of knowledge. In this unit we will deal
with the understanding of rationalism as a philosophical system, its method of
investigation and finally a detailed study of the method developed by the
various rationalist philosophers.
2.2 UNDERSTANDING RATIONALISM
Rationalism derives from the Latin word “Ratio”
meaning “Reason". In
Epistemological sense, Rationalism is "any view appealing to reason as a
source of knowledge or justification”. In a more technical term it is a method
or a theory "in which the criterion of the truth is not sensory but
intellectual and deductive. Rationalism
holds that genuine knowledge cannot come from sense perception or experience
but must have its foundation in thought or reason. It makes reason instead of
revelation and authority as the standard of knowledge. To employ reason is to use our individual
intellectual abilities to seek evidence for and against potential beliefs. To
fail to employ reason is to form beliefs on the basis of such non-rational
processes as blind faith, guessing or unthinking obedience to institutional
authority. Rationalism gives emphasis on the a priori reason which means
knowledge obtained prior to experience. It is universal, necessary and self
evident. Hence this theory holds that certain ideas like ideas of causality,
infinity and perfect being of God are inborn and highly indubitable.
Rationalism is also commonly called as Continental Rationalism, the term
‘continental rationalism’ would traditionally refer to a 17th century
philosophical movement begun by Descartes. After Descartes several scientists
and philosophers continued his teachings throughout continental Europe and
accordingly were titled as Cartesians. A handful of philosophers influenced by
Descartes were more original in developing their own views and they are
Benedict Spinoza, Nicholas Malebranche and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz..
2.3 RATIONAL METHOD OF INVESTIGATION
Continental rationalists in understanding the origin
of knowledge accepted the idea of innate and a priori truths which do not
depend on experience, although psychologically perception of them may be on the
occasion of an experience. They maintained that we could deduce truths with
absolute certainty from our innate ideas, much the way theorems in geometry are
deduced from axioms. Mathematical demonstration was seen as the perfect type of
demonstrating truth and accordingly mathematical proof became the model for all
other kinds of demonstration. For them Mathematics provides a model of clarity,
certainty and orderly deduction. The personal elements the subjective factors
such as feelings and emotions are eliminated and body of presuppositions the
truth of which is assured and built up. Although the empiricist used the same
deductive reasoning but they put a greater emphasis on the inductive method
following the British country man Francis Bacon. Thus rational method is basically predicting
and explaining behavior based on mathematical reasoning and logic.
Check Your Progress I
2.4 DESCARTES’ RATIONAL METHOD
Fundamental aim of Descartes was to attain
philosophical truths by the use of reason. But what he was seeking was not to
discover a multiplicity of isolated truths but to develop a system of true
prepositions in which nothing would be presupposed which was not self-evident
and indubitable. And the whole edifice should rest on a sure foundation. In one
sense Descartes consciously and deliberately broke with the past and did not
rely on any previous philosophy. He resolved to rely on his own reason and not on
authority. He was against what is conjectural of which he accused the
scholastics. Knowledge for him was only certain knowledge. He was determined to
attain and work with clear and distinct ideas in contrast to confused ideas and
in contrast to terms (scholastics) without any clear meaning. He built his own
interconnected system of knowledge, comprising an account of knowledge,
metaphysics, physics and other sciences.
This ambition is summarized in one of his last
writings as “all philosophy is like a tree, metaphysics is the roots it starts
with the intuitively apprehended existence of the finite self and proceeds to
establish the criterion of truth, existence of God and the existence of
material world. Physics is the trunk of the tree and it depends on metaphysics
in the sense physics cannot be considered organic part of science until the
ultimate principles of physics have been shown to follow metaphysical
principles. Particle sciences which are the branches of the tree will be truly
science when their organic dependence on physics or natural philosophy is
shown.
For Descartes tree of knowledge was its hierarchical
organization. He held firmly to the notion that the interconnected body of
knowledge has a particular order. For him knowledge begins in metaphysics and
metaphysics begins with the self. From the self we arrive at God and from God
we arrive at the full knowledge of mind and body. Thus he over throws the accumulation of
life-long beliefs and use reason alone to establish solid and permanent truths.
Truths should confirm to a rational scheme. Ideal philosophy means organically
connected system of scientifically established truths. This shows not only
systematic arrangement and a proof was his aim but believed in the use of
method that would enable the philosopher to discover hitherto unknown truths.
Cartesian
Method of Investigation
In his method to attain absolutely certainty and
universally acceptable knowledge Descartes wanted a certain and undubitable
starting point that even a radical could not shake the edifice of his
philosophical method. Expressing perfect confidence in the capacity of human
reason to achieve knowledge, Descartes wanted to accept only what is genuinely
certain as valid knowledge in his method. In order to do that one must first
deliberately renounce all of the firmly held but questionable beliefs
previously acquired by experience and education. Thus in his second part of the
Discourse on the Method he characterized four simple rules for his rational
method. 1) Accept as true only what is indubitable. Never to accept anything as
true if one does not have evident knowledge of its truth: that is carefully to
avoid precipitate conclusions and preconceptions. 2) One must analyze
difficulties into as many simpler parts as possible. 3) One must advance from
the simplest and most easily known objects to ascend little by little to
knowledge of the most complex. 4) One must ensure that nothing had been omitted
it is to make enumerations so complete and reviews so comprehensive. Therefore
this Cartesian method means a set of certain and easy rules such that anyone
who observes them exactly will never take anything false to be true without any
waste of mental effort but by increasing his knowledge step by step, will
arrive at a true understanding of all those things which do not surpass his
capacity.
Mathematics
as the foundation
In order to do this he employs mathematics as the
foundational tool. Mathematics must be the guide to clear the confusions and
uncertainties of philosophy. He looked at mathematics as mode of clear and
dubitable reasoning, because it consists of the use of two mental operations
they are Intuition: an immediate knowledge of anything. It is supposed to be
direct and impeccable. It is the understanding of self-evident principles about
which no doubts are possible. Self-evident principle is anything that does not
require any proof to establish itself. Deduction: Is a logical inference from
self-evident propositions. A valid conclusion can be arrived by proceeding from
generalizations to particular. Therefore Descartes quest for certainty and his
looking for mathematics as a model of reasoning was due to the revival of
skepticism. Which was one of the aspects of Renaissance Charron’s fideism (he
was skeptical of reason – theological truths can never be attained by reason,
only by faith) and Montaigne’s
skepticism. It is this that led to set philosophy on a sure basis. This
quasi mathematical procedure for the achievement of knowledge is typical of a
rational approach. This method is also called as the method of Doubt.
Doubt and
Certainty
Descartes insisted that the task of his method is to
rid oneself of all prejudices by calling in doubt all that can be doubted. The
path even to certainty begins with doubt. The doubting process frees oneself
from all preconceived opinions and provides one the easiest route by which the
mind may be led away from senses. It is a methodic doubt because he doubts not
for the sake of doubting but as a primary stage in the attainment of certainty
and for shifting the true from the false. In this way the skeptical doubt
prepares the mind for certainty. The first step towards certainty is the
discovery of the existence of the self. There is one thing that cannot be
doubted. That is the doubt itself which is certain. If doubt or thinking is
real than the doubter or thinker is also real. If the thinker is real than the
objects whatever comes into his contact are real therefore he come to
conclusion “Cogito ergo sum” ‘I am thinking therefore I exist.’ This cogito
argument not only derives a proof for his existence but also sought to discover
the essence to demonstrate the existence of God and to provide the criterion to
guide the mind in its search for truth. Thus this argument is to build the
entire world from the thinking self. It is important here that it is not just
the mind that is the foundation, but my mind. In this way the starting point of
philosophy for him was connected with the rejection of authority.
2.5
LEIBNIZ’S AIM OF PHILOSOPHY
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz a German philosopher,
mathematician and logician shared Descartes concern with what he called the
improvement of the sciences’ meaning the advancement of knowledge which would
render it secure against the possibility of serious doubt and error. Like
Descartes he felt that the various sciences and our so called knowledge
generally are not properly grounded and lack the certainty and freedom from the
possibility of error and so wanted to provide for a foundation for knowledge.
As Descartes he too was very much impressed with mathematics. His philosophical
method was modeled on mathematics hoping to get a comparable exactness and
certainty of our reasoning about reality.
He was critical of his method and procedure of
Descartes on a number of counts. Leibniz believed that there are two great
principles directing our reasoning. The
principle of contradiction: it is by means which we decide to be false that
which involves contradiction and that to be true which is opposed to the false.
It states that a thing cannot simultaneously be itself and another and the
immediate evidence of sense data. The
principle of sufficient reasoning: According to it if a being exists, it does
so because there is a sufficient reason for its existence. It asserts that
there is an adequate reason to account for the existence and nature of
everything that could conceivable not exist. We may not know all the reasons
from its existence. But there should be sufficient reason to be so. It is
different from principle of causality and the principle of identity. Eg. What
is the sufficient reasoning as to why I am a man not a table? It is because I
am a human substance. This principle affirms that everything that exists is
accounted for in a rationalistic and orderly world.
From these principles Leibniz contends that the
rules of common logic may be derived. To avoid all errors it is enough that one
sticks to common rules of logic with great constancy and rigour. It is not
necessary first to prove that existence and goodness of God which is not
possible without these rules anyhow.
Thus for Leibniz there was not only the two principles and indeed
something more to start with than Descartes Cogito ergo sum. There are other
truths. That is the particular contents of our immediate experience. What is
immediately given is not simply that I think but also that I have the
particular thoughts or perceptions I do. They do not guarantee that there
exists anything independent of them, corresponding to them but they themselves
are not subject to doubt. There are as many primary truths of the act as there
are immediate perceptions. Therefore what is truth are how will one establish
that truth?
Types of
truth
In his method he holds that the truth is to be
established by combining the simplest and most basic elements of knowledge. The
key idea here is the distinction between truth of reasoning and the truths of
facts. This is yet another contribution of Leibniz. The truths of reasoning (a
priori) are necessary and eternal truths, their opposite is impossible. Their
denial can only lead to contradiction. For example: “a triangle had three
sides.” They are also analytical that is the predicate of the Truth of
Reasoning is already pre-contained in the subject itself. Eg. Two and two is
four. Such truths are arrived through analysis and reasoning. The opposite of
such truths is indeed false and not possible at all.
Truths of Facts: The truths of fact (a posteriori)
are contingent and their opposite is possible. It is not arrived by rational
analysis but by experience of the fact. These truths are synthetic that is an
external reason is needed to equate the subject and the predicate in their
propositions. However the predicates of the TF are also virtually pre-contained
in the subject. One who has a vast and extensive knowledge of the subject would
be able to know all its contingent possibilities. Thus in his method Leibniz
has a rather low opinion of the importance of empirical knowledge. He is much
more interested what can be discovered about general nature of things through
the use of reason alone. It is this main reliance upon reason as opposed to
experiment and his conviction that reason can reveal to us the basic structure
of reality despite the limitation applying to empirical knowledge accounts for
the traditional designation of Leibniz as rationalist.
2.6 SPINOZA’S AIM OF PHILOSOPHY
Spinoza a Dutch-Jewish philosopher expounded part of
Descartes philosophy. In Spinoza’s view the proper order of philosophical
argument demands that we should start with that which is ontologically and
logically prior, namely with the divine essence or Nature and then proceed by
logically deducible stages. In adopting this approach Spinoza separated himself
from Descartes. In this endeavor to give a rational explanation of the world
speculative metaphysicians have always tended towards the reduction of
multiplicity to unity. Explanation in this connection means explanation in
terms of causality and so they have tended to reduction of multiplicity to
unity. In this sense Spinoza was a metaphysician with the ambitious aim of
explaining reality or making the universe intelligible. For him the fundamental
philosophical vision was one of unification and synthesis. Man’s happiness
consists in attaining the truth. Hence he was concerned with the method of
attaining truth and not about the capacity of the mind to know truth. In order
to attain truth the mind must get rid of various prejudices that distract us.
For example the prejudice that God and nature are not one. Thus in his book
Treatise on the correction of the understanding he speaks of three levels of
the method of knowing.
Levels of
Knowing
Imagination: We can first of all look at things ‘sub
specie temporis’ i.e under the aspect of ‘here and now’ time. This takes place
when we use imagination. This corresponds approximately to sensation. Our
bodies are affected by other bodies passively and through this affection we
come to know them. The knowledge of universal ideas also belongs to this level.
Through opinion or imagination we neither perceive things in themselves nor
infer them from the clear ideas of their causes. We nevertheless rely on ideas
of this kind in our common life and this is therefore a useful source of
knowledge. Imaginations give us vague, generalized and inadequate information.
Reason:
Sometimes we employ reasoning to view reality as separated, isolated and
distinct. The object of reason is common notions which are self-evident
principles of mathematics and physics. This knowledge is already scientific but
it is not the highest cognition because common notions and the conclusions
inferred from them are abstract. They do not represent the essence of things in
the richness of totality.
Intuition:
We also view things in “sub specie aeternitatis” or under the aspect of
eternity. We are able to glimpse the essential inter-relatedness of things.
This is the most perfect level of knowing. Here we have perception of the
individual things in all their fullness.
This is a natural process of knowing which begins with the perception of
individual unrelated phenomena, continues through the common notions or
abstract principles of thinking and ends in a full and gratifying version of
all things in God. On the criterion of truth he supplemented the ideas of
Descartes. For Descartes clarity and distinctness was the criterion of truth,
instead for Spinoza coherence is another criterion.
The
Geometrical Method
Spinoza applied Geometrical method in order to
explain the nature of God and world. This method had been propounded by the
most prominent mathematician Euclid (300 BC, Alexandria, Egypt). It deals with
the laws concerning lines, angles, planes etc. he handled the problem of the
world as a problem of geometry. According to him everything is said to follow
the first principle or ground of the universe as necessarily as the
propositions. He assumed without
questions that it is possible to construct a system of metaphysics that will
render it completely intelligible. The method guarantees true conclusions if
only the axioms are true and the definitions are correct. Spinoza’s abstract
entities also apply to reality as such. Thus we have a real definition an
adequate, true or clear and distinct idea of things. Although Spinoza uses the
geometrical method in the Ethica ordine Geometrico Demonstrata (Ethics
Demonstrated in Geometrical Manner), he does not attempt to justify or even
explain it. This has led many readers to view its argument as an intricate and
fascinating chain of reasoning from arbitrary premises, which as such never
touches reality.
2.7 LET US SUM UP
In order to provide a solid foundation to philosophy
one has to adopt a solid and sound method. The rationalists in and through
their methods have given a strong foundation for philosophy. Their emphasis on
reason as a tool to discover truth brought in a new dimensional change in the
western thought, especially the paradigm shift took by Kant in the history of
western philosophy. Rational method by using mathematics and its operations of
intuition and deduction has eliminated the the personal and subjective factors
such as feelings and emotions from of the body of truth. As a result it has
given truth a rational scheme in other words it has demonstrated truth is a
rational and systematic order.
2.8. KEY
WORDS
A priori – truths which do not depend on experience
A posteriori – truths which do depend on experience
UNIT
3 EMPIRICAL METHOD
Contents
3.0 Objectives
3.1 Introduction
3.2 Common
Features of Philosophical Method
3.3 Empirical
Method
3.4 Exposition
of Empiricism
3.5 Locke’s
Empirical Method
3.6 Berkeley’s
Empirical Method
3.7 David
Hume’s Empirical Method
3.6 Let
us Sum up
3.7 Key
Words
3.8 Further
Readings and References
3.0 OBJECTIVES
Earlier concepts of the existence of "innate
ideas" were the subject of debate between the Continental rationalists and
the British empiricists in the 17th century through the late 18th century. John
Locke, George Berkeley and David Hume were the primary exponents of empirical
method. The empirical method held that
all essential truths about the world were discoverable only by empirical
experience i.e sense experience. It is a process of arriving at truth through
experiential verification of perceived data. Hence in this method reason was
substituted by experience. The unit
exposes the empirical method adopted by these three above mentioned
philosophers.
3.1 INTRODUCTION
The term method is derived from a Greek word
“methodos” – road to. Etymologically the term refers to the way of doing
something, the system of procedure to obtain or reach the end intended. It is a
way of procedure from the known to the unknown, from the given starting point
to final propositions in a determined field of knowledge. In sciences the use
of correct methods is most important in order to make certain that the
conclusions are correctly connected with the starting point and the foundation.
Every scientific method is the road from the known starting point to a result.
And one of the characteristic features of the discipline of philosophy is the
existence of method. Philosophical method (or philosophical methodology) is the
study of how to do philosophy. So a method of doing philosophy, or a
philosophical method, is a systematic or patterned way of answering
philosophical questions.
But within them the questions in philosophy are
always local in the sense that they carry favor of their own peculiar time and
circumstances as a result they do not remain quite the same over a period of
time the methods adopted to obtain answers for them have also changed over a
period of time. This is especially evident if we look at the evolution of
philosophical methods in western philosophy from the speculative, dialectical,
empirical, rational method to that of analytical, phenomenological,
transcendental method. This evolution
and proliferation of different methods in western philosophy seem to close
links with the way science and philosophy began developing in 17th century.
When science started to develop quite fast due to the impetus received from the
work of Galileo, Newton and others two powerful and influential methods in
philosophy – rationalism and empiricism also quickly developed. Of course,
there is not just one method that philosophers use to answer philosophical
questions. But it is possible to draw some valid generalizations or common
features that include while discussing philosophical methods.
3.2 COMMON FEATURES OF PHILOSOPHICAL METHOD
Doubt: Notice doubts that one has about the meaning
or justification of some common, everyday belief one has. Formulate a problem: Formulate the doubts in
a philosophical problem, or question. Explain the problem very clearly and
carefully. Offer a solution: Offer a
solution to the problem: either something like a philosophical analysis or a
philosophical explanation. Argument: Give an argument or several arguments
supporting the solution. Dialectic: Present the solution and arguments for
criticism by other philosophers, and help them judge their own.
3.3 EMPIRICAL METHOD
Empirical method is generally taken to mean ‘the
collection of data’ on which to base a theory or derive a conclusion in
science. The term "empirical" was originally used to refer to certain
ancient Greek practitioners of medicine who rejected adherence to the dogmatic
doctrines of the day, preferring instead to rely on the observation of
phenomena as perceived in experience. An empiric is "one who, either in
medicine or in other branches of science, relies solely upon observation and
experiment. The empirical method is not
sharply defined and is often contrasted with
the experimental method, where data are derived from the systematic
manipulation of variables in an experiment. Some of the difficulty in
discussing the empirical method is from the ambiguity of the meaning of its
linguist root: empiric. According to the Oxford English Dictionary (2nd
Edition, 1989), empiric is derived from the ancient Greek for experience,
έμπειρία, which is ultimately derived from έυ (in )+ πεἳρα (trial) or
experiment. Therefore, empirical data is information that is derived from the
trials and errors of experience. In this way, the empirical method is similar
to the experimental method. However, an essential difference is that in an
experiment the different "trials" are strictly manipulated so that an
inference can be made as to causation of the observed change that results. This
contrasts with the empirical method of aggregating naturally occurring data. In
philosophy too an empirical method refers to a practice of knowledge derived
entirely from sense perception or experience. It is a process of attaining
truth through experiential verification of perceived data. It is a method which
interprets philosophy from a world of experience. But in order to understand
the entire process of empirical method one needs to study what first Empiricism
is and philosophers who have contributed to this philosophical trend.
3.4 EXPOSITION OF EMPIRICISM
The modern philosophy can be generally classified as
rationalistic and empiricistic as they accept reason or experience respectively
as the source and norm of knowledge. According to the empiricist view, for any
knowledge to be properly inferred or deduced, it is to be gained ultimately
from one's sense-based experience. As a historical matter, philosophical
empiricism is commonly contrasted with the philosophical school of thought
known as rationalism which, in very broad terms, asserts that much knowledge is
attributable to reason independently of the senses.
In philosophy empiricism holds the attitude that
beliefs are to be accepted and acted upon only if they first have been
confirmed by actual experience. This broad definition accords with the
derivation of the name from the Greek word ‘Empeiria’, which corresponds to the
Latin ‘experientia’ which in turn takes the English meaning ‘experience’.
Empiricism is a system of thought which believes that there are no inborn
truths and all knowledge springs from sense perception or experience and there
is no absolutely certain knowledge without experiential verification of the
perceived data. Reason can yield only probable knowledge. Empiricism thus holds
that our world of experience is the object of philosophy and all knowledge is
ultimately based on experience. Experience so understood has a variety of modes
– sensory, aesthetic, moral, religious and so on but empiricist concentrate on
sense experience. It goes to an extent of affirming that there is no other
knowledge except that which comes from experience.
There are two kinds of empiricism one is a stronger
form and other in a weaker. Such distinction has to do with scope – whether the
view takes all knowledge to be based on experience or restricts this claim to
knowledge of the physical universe, eluding for example mathematical and/or
religious knowledge. Material Empiricism: The stronger form of empiricism is
called material empiricism. It holds that the objectively existing outer world
is the source of sense experience. It puts forward that the only things that
shall be debatable among philosophers shall be things definable in terms drawn
from experience. Idealist Empiricism: It is a weaker form which limits
experience to the sum total of sensations. Sensation is a kind of physical
state occurring as a result of direct influence of the objects on the sense
experience. It is also of two types namely External and Internal. External
sensation is caused by any one of senses like sense of sight, touch, taste,
sound and smell. Internal sensation is caused by reflection or psychical acts
of human mind.
Characteristics
of Empiricism
According to empiricism human mind at birth is
“tabula rasa” or a clean slate. The mind is being compared to a blank writing
tablet, white paper and void of all characters. It is in original state a
mental blankness. The mind is only potential or inactive before receiving ideas
from the senses. Sense experience as source of knowledge. Sensation and
reflection the outer and the inner sense experience is the only windows through
which the dark chamber of mind comes to be filled with light. Empiricism does
not deal with universals. It holds that universal propositions can
satisfactorily be explained by particulars. Empiricism denies intuition which
enables us to grasp general truths about reality independently of experience as
a result it accepts only inductive method which is a process of reasoning from
a part to a whole, from particulars to generals, individuals to universals.
3.5 LOCK’S EMPIRICAL METHOD
John lock was suspicious of the view that a thinker
could work out by reason alone the truth about the universe. In response to the
early-to-mid-17th century Continental Rationalism of Rene Descartes and Baruch
Spinoza in the later 17th century John Locke (1632–1704) proposed in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
(1689) a very influential view wherein the only knowledge humans can have is a
posteriori, i.e., based upon experience.
All materials of human knowledge are derived from experience either of
the external world through our senses or of our own mental life through
introspection. He established that all our ideas derive from experience that is
the way we conceive the world (including ourselves). Therefore, he set the tone for the empiricist method by
affirming the foundational principle of empiricism; “there is nothing in the
intellect that was not previously In the senses .” (nihil est in intellectu
quod non antea fuerit in sensu). All knowledge of the world must finally rests
on human sense experience.
Thus Locke is famously attributed for holding the
proposition that the human mind is a Tabula Rasa, a "blank tablet,"
in Locke's words "white paper," on which the experiences derived from
sense impressions as a person's life proceeds are written. Through the
combining and compounding of simple sense impressions or ideas (defined as
mental contents) into more complex concepts the mind can arrive at sound
conclusions. In his empirical method Lock vehemently attacked the doctrine of
innate ideas according to him ideas are acquired, learned and obtained from our
experience. They are immediate objects of our sensory awareness. They are
sensory presentation of physical objects both external and internal. They are
concepts that we gain through introspection of our own mental operations like
meditation.
There are two sources of our ideas: sensation and
reflection. In both cases, a distinction is made between simple and complex
ideas. Simple ideas are those that result from pure passivity and consist of a
single content. These are obtained through experience alone and are directly
known as the contents of actual experience Ex. Colour, hear extensity etc.,
Lock calls them as primary qualities Those ideas which, come from more than one
sense organ (solidity, motion, number,
shape…)and the secondary those ideas that are from one sense organ and are the
ways in which facts affect us (colour, smell, sound …). Complex ideas are formed
by the synthesis of two or more simple ideas. Here the mind is active. Mind has the power to repeat, compare,
compound the simple ideas in endless variety and thus make complex ideas. This
process of compounding and comparing are the operations of the mind. The number
of ideas formed by compounding and comparing is almost infinite but they can be
classified into Modes themselves, substance and relation.
Modes: Modes are the complex ideas that cannot exist
by themselves they are represented by others they are simple modes and Mixed
modes,. The former same simple ideas without any mixture of any other whereas
the later is components of simply ideas of various kinds put together to make a
complex one. Substance: The existence of modes presupposes that of substance.
It is the substratum as the cause for the unity of modes. Relation: Here mind
gets certain ideas of relation by comparing one thing with another. The idea of
cause and effect. Thus his empirical method establishes the hold that the mind
is at first a blank tablet, a passive receptor of its experience. The mind
possesses innate powers but not innate ideas as cognition begins only with
sensation.
3.6 BERKELEY’S EMPERICAL METHOD
One of the aims of Berkeley’s philosophy is to
attack scepticism and thereby to defend common sense and to attack atheism and
thereby to defend religion. Against them
he held that the reality of the physical world is essentially spiritual for it
manifests the activity of spirit and goodness of God’s will. Mind or spirit is
the only substance and that it is God who produces sensations or ideas in our
mind. According to him secondary qualities are not objective. They change and
are not perceived in exactly the same way by everyone. Therefore they are more in the mind than of
the things.
As a result his empirical method is viewed by many
as having some idealistic tenants as it teaches that reality consists of
spirits and their ideas only. This is
known as immanent idealism. According to this doctrine human mind can possess
or acquire the knowledge of their own experiences. However he established this
idealistic conclusion as the implication of his famous maxim “esse est
percepi.” Since there is nothing as an objective material substance it follows
that for material things to be is to be perceived. Esse is act of being or
literally to be and its percipi is nothing but to be perceived. It is not
possible that they have and existence out of the minds or thinking things which
perceive them. His method implies that
our thoughts, passions, pictures of imagination do not exist outside the mind,
they are in the mind and their existence consists in their being perceived or
known by the mind. Objects exist in so far s they are perceive. In other words
to be is to be perceived. The objects are existing because the finite minds
perceive them. Even if the finite minds do not perceive the objects still they
exist because an ever vigilant spectator perceives them all through. Such an
ever vigilant spectator is none other than God (infinite mind or spirit). In
short Berkeley points out all mental representations of supposed material
substance are finally ideas in the mind therefore the existence of a material
world external to the mind is unwarranted assumption. To do does not mean to be a material
substance rather to be means to be perceived by mind.
3.7 DAVID HUME’S EMPIRICAL METHOD (1711–1776)
It was his great desire to establish a science of
human nature. After all every science has to do with human nature in some way
or the other, whether it is logic, mathematic etc. Man and it is he who
ultimately decides what is true and what is false in these disciplines. Thus it
is evident that human nature is the capital or centre of the various sciences
and it should therefore serve as their focal point. Hume’s aim was then to explain the principles
of human nature so that all the various disciplines might be able to build upon
the solid foundation. In order to do
that he advocated experimental method to establish this science. This method is
based on observation and experience. We must make a close and accurate
observation of man’s psychological processes and moral behavior and try to
separate out from these the various laws according to which man works – just as
is done in the natural science. Thus rather than relying on supposed
intellectual intuitions of the essences of the human mind through
introspection, one shall make use of the more scientifically solid procedure of
induction. Thus his view is empirical in
the sense that our knowledge has its source in experience.
He argues that all knowledge derives from sense
experience. In particular, he divided all of human knowledge into two
categories: relations of fideas and matters of fact. Mathematical and logical
propositions (e.g. "that the square of the hypotenuse is equal to the sum
of the squares of the two sides") are examples of the first, while
propositions involving some contigent observation of the world (e.g. "the
sun rises in the East") are examples of the second. All of people's
"ideas", in turn, are derived from their "impressions".
There are two types of impressions outward impressions and inward
impressions. From such impressions all
our knowledge is derived. For Hume, an
"impression" corresponds roughly with what we call a sensation. To
remember or to imagine such impressions is to have an "idea". Ideas
are therefore the faint copies of sensations. Thus according to Hume there is
no absolute or certain knowledge of matters of fact. Our knowledge never
reaches absolute certainty. We base our conclusion on experience. As a simple
instance posed by Hume, we cannot know with certainty by inductive reasoning
that the sun will continue to rise in the East, but instead come to expect it
to do so because it has repeatedly done so in the past. Thus David Hume drove the empiricist method
to its logical end making use of Berkeley’s insight at the same time turning
towards modern secular skepticism. As an empiricist who grounded all human
knowledge in sense experience, still Hume disagreed with Locke’s representative
perception and Berkeley’s idealistic solution. Human experience is indeed of
the phenomenal only and there is no way to ascertain what is beyond it.
3.8 LET US SUM UP
Empirical method paved way of very practical basis
for philosophy. It said pure rationality or making use of reason as the only
tool of knowledge will led philosophy to a baseless ground. Therefore, one
needs to start from the given form the sense perception or experience. Out mind
cannot act, reason cannot perform its function unless something is carried on
to it in and through the sense experiences. Truth or discovery of truth is
basically through the a posteriori. Though the empirical method has its own
drawbacks still it served a valid basis for demonstration of truth.
3.9 KEY WORDS
Tabula Rasa – word used by Locke to refer to the
emptiness of the mind before experience
Innate ideas
– refers to the inborn ideas
UNIT 4 CRITICAL METHOD
Contents
4.0 Objectives
4.1 Introduction
4.2 Basic
Features of Critical Theory
4.3 On
Instrumental Reason
4.4 Conception
of Society
4.5 Human
History as Dialectic of Enlightenment
4.6 Subtantive
Reason
4.7 Habermasian
Critical Theory
4.8 Habermas’
Theory of Soceity
4.9 Habermas’
Critique of Scientism
4.10 Theory
of Communicative Action
4.11 Discourse
Ethics of Habermas
4.12 Let us
Sum up
4.13 Key
Words
4.14 Further
Readings and References
4.0 OBJECTIVES
• To
introduce a method of philosophizing that was prevalent in the twentieth
century
• To
familiarize the students to the world of critical thinking, social critique and
ideological structuring
• To
have a overall picture of Critical theory developed and promoted by Frankfort
school of philosophy which has a tremendous impact in the continental
philosophy of our times.
4.1 INTRODUCTION
Critical Method is the critical theorist approach to
the study of society. As a theory, it was developed between 1930-1970 by
‘Frankfurt school’ group of theorists and philosophers like Max Horkheimer,
Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno, Herbert Marcuse and Hebermas. It begins by
critiquing the modern Western societies that became closed and totalitarian
societies where all individual freedom and autonomy were at stake. As a result
of the capitalist mode of production, they believed early, that the societies
turn into totalitarian. Later they focused on the role of science and
technology in modern society, and the ‘instrumental’ conception of reason. This conception denies the possibility of
inherent rational ends of human action and affirms reason as exclusive choice
of effective instruments for achieving arbitrary ends. If ‘instrumental
rationality’ is not subordinated to a more encompassing notion of rationality,
it would bring in disastrous consequences. Critical theorists reflected on the
impossibility of leading a good life in the contemporary world. Critical method
is a form of cultural criticism and more a theoretical commitment than action
for radical social change.
4.2 BASIC
FEATURES OF CRITICAL THEORY
Many critics and intellectuals in Frankfurt School
adapt Marxism to the theoretical and political needs of their time. The
distinguishing feature of their approach is their theoretical orientation in
social sciences for a critical theory of society. Method of the Critical
theorists was to offer an internal or immanent criticism in form of resistance
to the contemporary society. For them,
every society claims to have substantive rationality and to allow its members
to lead a good life. Critical method takes such claim as a standard for
criticism. Critical theory method exposes such societies that fail to live up
to their own claims. Understanding of good life from the beliefs, cultural
artefacts and forms of experience present in the society is analysed and
criticised in critical method. This serves as a basis for internal criticism.
However, they find in the contemporary society a particular difficulty of
finding these traditional substantive conceptions of the good life. These have been replaced by a justification
that modern society needs no legitimation beyond its actual efficient
functioning and to its ‘instrumental’ rationality. Hence ‘instrumental
rationality’ itself becomes a major target for critical theory. (Geuss 1998)
Critical theory began with a social theory guided by
an interest in the normative goal of human emancipation. They were skeptical of
the enlightenment assumption of scientific and technological progress as an
unproblematic human good. Empirical science was based on ‘instrumental
rationality,’ which is inherently manipulative. It has brought in disastrous
social and moral consequences.
They rejected a commonly held view of a ‘theory’ as
a set of formally specified and interconnected general propositions which is
used for successful explanation and prediction of the phenomena. This
conception is extremely misleading. It
takes away the social context in which theory arose, tested and applied. Without
the context theories are not fully comprehensible. For the critical theorists, the term ‘theory’
designates a form of social activity. Human societies are engaged in a constant
process of assimilating nature through labour in order to reproduce themselves;
they develop forms of cognitive activity in order to make this
self-reproduction more secure and more efficient. Cognitive activity is
‘traditional theory,’ from which the so called scientific theories are derived.
Such cognitive activity not only directed at reproducing society but also at
changing the existing society radically. (Geuss 1998)
4.3 ON
INSTRUMENTAL REASON
‘Reason’ was objective in ancient world and was
thought to refer to a structure o order inherent in reality. Human beings were
thought to have a subjective faculty to perceive and respond to that objective
structure of the world. It was used to determine goals of humans.
In the post-Enlightenment world the ‘objective’
conception of reason becomes increasingly implausible. Reason comes to be
conceived as essentially a subjective ability to find efficient means to
arbitrarily given ends. Reason becomes subjective, formal and instrumental. It
is identified with the kind of reason used in natural science. Scientific
reason, obtained from the instrumental understanding reason, is used to
manipulate the world towards human ends. Reason becomes a guide to life only in
a very limited sense. But reason goes beyond those limits and retains its
internal and immanent critical character. (Geuss 1998)
4.4 CONCEPTION OF SOCIETY
Positivists held that the human societies are just
bundles of separates facts, events and institutions. Social facts and
institutions are what they are objectively. The concepts of society are purely
descriptive and defined in terms of observable properties. These concepts are
just tools that humans can define in whatever way seems convenient. Critical
theorists totally reject all these understanding of society. For them, every
society is a ‘totality’ in which each feature is essentially connected with all
others. Social reality is partly constituted by forms of belief, understanding
and evaluation. The facts and institutions are not objective but inherently
oriented towards the realization of specified conception of the good life. As
each society has an objective concept of itself as an ideal form of itself,
every institution in it is to be evaluated in relation to that concept towards
the realization of the good life. To discover the concept is a very complex,
constructive, theoretical activity. The method of critical theory is to elicit
the concept of a given institution in a given society, formulate it and
confront the actual reality of the institution with this ideal concept. If
there are discrepancies, it would be exposed and analysed. Such method is
called internal or immanent criticism. Adorno says that one cannot extract from
reason the image of a good society as reason cannot describe utopia.
4.5 HUMAN HISTORY AS DIALECTIC OF
ENLIGHTENMENT
For Horkheimer and Adorno, human history is a
dialectic of ‘enlightenment’ on the one hand and ‘myth/barbarism’ on the other.
‘Enlightenment’ is a certain theory, a specification of goals for society, a
set of views about individual morality the nature of knowledge, rationality and
so on. It is also the actual state of society resulting from the above. ‘Myth’
is ‘barbarism’ opposed to ‘enlightenment’. Enlightenment as a theory has
commitment to certain ideals like autonomy, individuality, human happiness.
Genuine knowledge, according to it, is knowledge that is objectifying, identifying
and inherently technologically efficacious. Increase in such genuine knowledge
in a society would lead to realization of ideals. Nothing is taken on faith or
authority or tradition.
Critical theorist claim that all formulations of
enlightenment as seen in the previous paragraph, is false. Enlightenment is not
utterly and radically different from myth. The relation between myth and
enlightenment is dialectical. Both have
a common origin as reactions to the same phenomenon: primeval terror, to deal
with fear of what is unknown. Myth is a mimetic reaction by making ourselves
like that which we fear, by identifying with it. It is an attempt to do away
with its primitive. The other way of
reacting to fear is by separating it fully from the self and subjecting it to
have control over it. The latter becomes
enlightenment. In myth we make ourselves like the other; in enlightenment we
try to make the other like our category by subsuming it. Myths are only
historically superseded forms of enlightenment. Moreover, myth and
enlightenment are not given absolutely once and for all, but is historically
relative.
Enlightenment has its own negative impact on
humanity with its instrumentally manipulative attitude in terms of relation
between human and nature and with fellow human beings. The effective
instrumental control led to repress the spontaneity, which is human,’s capacity
for happiness. Modern subjectivity in which self-preservation is ensured at the
cost of happiness, is the best example as a result of enlightenment.
Enlightenment has an inherent tendency to destroy itself. The ideals like
autonomy, individuality and so on are not exempt from the demands of the
principle of universal criticism. The increase in technological control over
the world and the spread of scientific knowledge has not made people more
autonomous, more highly individuated or happier. Finally, enlightenment is
potentially totalitarian and has an inherent tendency to absolutize itself.
Therefore, critical theorists have the task of enlightening the enlightenment
itself, by analyzing its inherent tendency towards totalitarianism, by saving
its ideals and by preventing it from turning
itself into a form of myth and barbarism.
4.6 SUBSTANTIVE REASON
Adorno gave an account of a thinking that is a form
of substantive reason. It is a kind of thinking constitutive of his critical
theory. For enlightened reason some
false beliefs are subjective projections. The medium of those projections like
senses, social practices and history, are systematic sources of error. So for
true knowledge the only condition is complete independence from these mediums.
The autonomy of reason and meaning-independence of concepts is explicitly
identified with the spontaneity of the ‘transcendental’ subject. This subject
and the philosophical concept of system from it are driven by self-preservation
due to both fear and rage against their objects. Adorno appropriates this
conception of idealism as rationalized rage which is directed at anything that
refuses to fit or non-identical with the demands of autonomous reason. This
autonomy of reason is secured through the meaning-independence of concepts from
concrete experience and its mediums. The particulars and contingents are
incommensurable with this reason. Adorno tries for the ‘rescue’ of nonidentity
- the thing in itself in its concrete, historically mediated sensuous
particularity by the use of dialectic.
We usually subsume particulars and individuals under
generality. Asserting of identity between the two individuals and between each
individual and the concept is taken for granted in every day thinking and
generally in science too. This Adorno calls as ‘identity thinking,’ which is
not true as in every individual there is a difference. ‘Identity thinking’ in a way crushes or
suppresses difference. For instance, X is a cow and ‘Y’ is another cow. We
subsume these two particulars as a general concept of ‘cow,’ and the third one
‘Z’ is also linked to this concept of ‘cow.’
By engaging ‘identity thinking’ we tacitly try to make these three
animals identical. In fact what is there is that there are three particular
animals which are different from one another.
Hence, it overlooks the differences. Critical theory tries to resist
such identity tactics and to remain aware of ‘non-identity.’ There are
instances where any given two are not identical with the concept that is
already made of subsuming one to the other.
Adorno demonstrated that the rationalized concept of
an object does not exhaust the thing conceived. The sensory images and other
mediums that are stripped away in the attainment of autonomy are the necessary
mediations through which knowing subjects come into relation to objects known.
Such a project of Adorno is called ‘Negative dialectics’ which continually
points out the concrete differences. It becomes a kind of cognition of the
non-identical and it goes on back and forth.
It would not stop in some positive or more adequate concept but a
continual negative dialectics. In applying this critical method in
philosophical writing, Adorno even rejected the usual standards of clarity and
communicability which he feared as forms of repression. It prevents, according
to him the novel thoughts and critical ideas from being ‘thoughts.’ Hence, we
find that he adopted an elusive style in writing and claimed that his
philosophy could not be summarized.
In summary, the critical theory of Horkheimer and
Adorno maintained capitalism, enlightenment, scientific era brought in mangy
disadvantages and suffering to humanity in the modern period. No doubt they
brought in various changes. Nevertheless, they led people to have guilt,
inadequacy and progressive political change contributing to a new barbarism. As
Adorno calls, they brought in nothing but a ‘real hell.’ From critiquing the
impact of enlightenment movement their concern was to expose the nexus of
rationality and social actuality. The ulterior dominating attitude of the
humans upon nature underlies the project of instrumental reason. Critical
theory exposed the rise and domination of instrumental reason while examining
the philosophy of the Enlightenment. By doing so, they hoped for a positive and
emancipatory notion of enlightenment. Their method in critical theory was to
release humanity from the entanglement and domination of philosophy of
instrumental reasoning which hailed enlightenment. The critical method is
directed at a particular society that stunts the possible realization of the
good life. It is inherently negative, and it depends on a conception of
substantive reason. Critical method paves a way for the play of free,
spontaneous, human subjectivity in an increasingly regimented world. It
remained as part of the ‘self consciousness of a revolutionary process of
social change.’
4.7 HABERMASIAN CRITICAL THEORY
Critical theory took a turn to more generalized
critique of instrumental rationality which finally culminated in Adorno’s
“negative dialectics.” For Habermas, with Horkheimer and Adorno, the critical
theory had reached its dead end. He sketched out a critical theory of modernity
that accounted for its pathology. He suggested a re-orientation of modernity
rather than abandoning the project of enlightenment. He proposed a shift of
paradigm for critical theory away from the philosophy of consciousness.
He had his interest in developing the concept of
rationality, which is beyond the individualistic and subjectivist premises of
modernity. He shared with other critical theorists that enlightenment in the
form of instrumental rationality became more a source of enslavement means than
a means of liberation. By his investigation of instrumental rationality that
dominated the modern thought, Habermas examined the loss of significance of the
epistemic subject and the capacity for reflection by the subject on his or her
activities. In the present effort of making rationality for emancipation, we
need to counter this tendency and re affirm the necessity of self reflection
for self-understanding.
Critical theory of society for Habermas is inherent
in the very structure of social action and language. If in any communicative
situation a consensus is established under coercion it is an instance of
systematically distorted communication. In proposing for the contemporary
formation of ideology and the process of emanciapation, Habermas advocates the
transcendence of such systems of distorted communication. Here again, what is
required is engagement in critical reflection and criticism where domination is
exposed.
4.8 HABERMAS’
THEORY OF SOCIETY
Habermas tried to develop a theory of society with a
practical intention. His concern was to offer a systematic and theoretical
account of the relation between theory and practice in all social sciences. By
doing this he intended to challenge the domination of scientism. He reflected
on the nature of cognition, the structure of social inquiry and the normative
basis of socio-cultural aspects of the society. He wanted to developed the
theory of society with practical intention. He was critical of the developments and
changes in the capitalist and socialist societies in the twentieth century
history that raised lots of doubt about the validity of Marxian analysis and
theory. It also posed a major concern
about the traditional social thoughts and values perpetuated by many
traditions, as they seemed to be bearing no impact on contemporary
society. It called for an assessment and
reformulation so as to be relevant today. The developments through scientific
revolution and enlightenment are juxtaposed with the developments in the notion
of freedom, justice, happiness and self-realization. The Western society has
witnessed rather the rise of nihilism and anti-modernism threatening the
project of modernity and enlightenment.
It paved a way also to dogmatism and superstition, fragmentation and
discontinuity with loss of meaning, as reactionary response to modernity. According to him, the growth of
rationalization has curtailed the freedom and self-determination of human
being. Technological progress brought in both blessings and difficulties. One cannot think of abandoning the
achievements of modernity. One needs to have a careful analysis of the outcome
of the progress of modernity. Critical theory, for Habermas had real potential
to overcome domination and repression and to further the process of human
emancipation. It is the distinguishing factor for Critical method from
traditional social theory. It is necessary, therefore according to him to
undertake the task of a scientific understanding of the dynamics of the
society. One has to appropriate the developments in the social sciences and
integrate them into a critical social science. He worked towards the notion of
just and emancipated society.
4.9 HABERMAS’ CRITIQUE OF SCIENTISM
Habermas attempted to construct an alternative to
the technological determinism. The technocratic consciousness in the level
social theory has made people to have a tendency to define practical problems
as technical issues. Such technocracy justifies a particular class interest in
domination and does not disclose the fundamental interests of humankind. It
threatens an essential aspect of human life and affects the very structure of
human interests. In his systematic critique of positivism and scientism Habermas
says that positivism insists that only the sciences constitute genuine
knowledge and believes that science does not need any further critical
analysis. It is a mere ‘scientific self-misunderstanding,’ which Habermas
challenges. He attempts to secure an independent basis for critique that all
forms of knowledge are rooted in fundamental human interests, namely
‘anthropologically deep-seated cognitive interests. These interests are vivid as technical
interest in natural sciences, as practical interest in historical-hermeneutic
sciences and as emancipatory interest in critical sciences. “The human interest
in autonomy and responsibility is not mere fancy, for it can be apprehended a
priori. What raises us out of nature is the only thing whose nature we can know:
language’ (1968: 314).
For Habermas the growth of technocracy was not
inevitable but the result of a failure to preserve the classical distinction
between theory and practice, and between practical wisdom and technical skill.
He traced this loss of distinction in modern political theories of Hobbes to
Hegel as well as of Marx. Marxian
concept of praxis blurred the distinction between labour and modes of social
interaction. Habermas argues that the end of alienated labour does not alone
ensure social emancipation. (Baynes 1998)
For Habermas, knowledge is historically rooted and
interest bound. Human beings are both toolmaking and language-using animals.
They had to produce from nature what is needed for their existence. It was done
by manipulation and controlof of objects and necessarilly communicated with
each other through the use of intersubjectively understood symbols of language.
Humankind has an interest in the creation of knowledge to control objectified
processes and to maintain communication. This is a basis of interests that human beings had to organize their
experience in terms of a priori interests. There is also an interest in reason,
in the human capacity to be self-reflective and self-determining, to act
rationally. It results in to generation of knowledge enhancing autonomy and
responsibility. It is an emancipatory interest. His theory of cognitive
interests elaborates the relationship of knowledge to human activity.
Further for examining the distinction between
processes of constitution and justification, he developed the theory of
communicative competence. All speech is oriented to the idea of a genuine
consensus which involves a nomative dimension.
This is formalized and attained in an ideal speech situation, where
consensus becomes a rational consensus and the ultimate criterion of truth.
Here the very structure of speech is held to involve the anticipation of a form
of life in which truth, freedom and justice are possible.
4.10 THEORY OF COMMUNICATIVE ACTION
The Theory of
Communicative Action (1981) is Habermas’ magnum opus. It is a
major contribution to social theory with reflections on the basic concepts of
social theory along with observations on the methodology of the social
sciences, hypotheses about modernization as a process of societal
rationalization. Habermas does not see social rationalization as a process that
culminates in the loss of meaning and freedom in the world, but as potential
for societal learning and human emancipation.
He makes a distinction between communicative action and
purposive-rational actions. The former is ‘content-oriented,’ whereas the
latter is ‘success-oriented,’ and goal oriented. The latter instrumental
actions are appraised from the standpoint of efficiency with following the
technical rules. They are strategic actions aiming at influencing others for
the purpose of achieving some end. Communicative action constitutes an
independent and distinct type of social action. The goal is not to influence
others but to reach an agreement or mutual understanding about something in the
world. The goal of the agent is subordinated to the goal of achieving a
mutually cooperative process of interpretation of the life-worldly situation.
The individuals with communicative action aim at understanding by relating
their interpretations by three basic types of speech acts: constative,
regulative and expressive. (1981, vol. I: 319-). Habermas forms it as
communicative rationality as it tries to criticize its own validity claims.
By communicative rationality Habermas does not see
society as sort of large-scale debating club. The agents’ interpretations are
taken for granted and form the background of knowledge and practices which is
called the life-world. Social integration is achieved in this way. Habermas’
distinction between society as life-world and society as system is a unique
feature in critical method. The society is an outcome of process of
rationalization and societal differentiation. Habermas emphasizes the potential
for emancipation through his theory of communicative action. Social pathologies
are not just because of rationalization but rather from a one-sided process
displacing modes of integration based on communicative reason with that of the
market and administrative state’s functional rationality. This is ‘colonization
of the life-world.’ (Baynes 1998)
4.11 DISCOURSE
ETHICS OF HABERMAS
Discourse ethics is communicative ethics. Habermas
develops this as an important corollary of theory of communicative action. This ethics is a formulation of a
post-conventional moral theory and an alternative to utilitarianism and Kantian
ethics. Discourse ethics is centered around the basic idea of principle of
universalizability that functions as a rule testing the legitimacy of norms.
The principle is as Habermas puts it, “Every valid norm must satisfy the
condition that all affected can accept the consequences and the side effects
its general observance can be anticipated to have for the satisfaction of
everyone’s interests (and these consequences are preferred to those of known
alternative possibilities).” (Habermas 1983: 65)
This principle is derived from the general pragmatic
presuppositions of communication and argumentation. In every commincation the
speakers have validity claims with ideal speech situations. The principle of
universalizability is an attempt to formulate counterfactual ideal.
Accordingly, the norms or maxims of action are only morally legitimate if, when
contested, they could be justified in a moral-practical discourse.
Discourse ethics does not presuppose substantive
moral content beyond the idea of practical reason. It specifies a formal
procedure which any norm must satisfy if it is to be morally acceptable. It
supposes an independent order of moral facts. Discourse ethics is a
deontological moral theory as it assumes the priority of the right over the
good. For Habermas morality consists not just of categorical imperatives but of
obligations in terms of communicative action. The valid norms are morally
binding as there is an intimate connection with processes of social interaction
and communication. (1983: 109).
Habermasian ethics differs from Kantian ethics as it
breaks the Kantian two-world metaphysics (phenomenal/noumenal) and rejects the
monological interpretation of the categorical imperative. Habermas favours an intersubjective or
communicative version of the principle of universalizability, even though in
Kant’s kingdom of ends one finds an inter-subjective dimension already. In
communicative ethics the ideal is in practical discourse. Discourse ethics
makes good its claim with a notion of rational consensus or rational
acceptability as the best general account of more ordinary moral
intuitions. The abstract notion of equal
respect implicit in the idea of communicative action is in contrast to Kantian
and Utilitarian attractive claims of respecting individual autonomy or
integrity and concern for the welfare of others or solidarity. Habermas
understanding of communicative rationality enhances agreement between subjects
rather than instrumental control of thing.
In his The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity
(1985), Habermas criticizes postmodern thought for resting modern philosophy of
consciousness against which its criticism is directed. The modern and contemporary philosophy dwells
either of the following positions: Subject is regarded as one object among
others in the world, or as a ‘transcendental’ subject. The paradigm shift is
necessary with a model of communicative action in which subjectivity is first approached
through the intersubjective relations of individuals with one another. In
short, modernity remains an ‘unfulfilled project,’ which is not to be abandoned
but to be amended. (Baynes 1998)
4.12 LET US
SUM UP
Critical theory emerged from a group of intellectuals
in Frankfurt, Germany, who studied social and economic issues in contemporary
society from socialist perspective. Critical theory is designated as the
approach to social theory developed initially by people like Max Horkheimer,
Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno and Herbert Marcuse and later by Habermas. They involved themselves with the forces,
which moved society towards rational institutions. They conceived of these
rational institutions as ensuring a true, free and just life, while at the same
time being aware of the obstacles, which rendered radical change untenable and
difficult. Critical theory developed in the background of various political and
historical events in the West especially between 1920s and 1930s that had
surely shaken many a Marxist followers. The Marxist theory of the day let down
the expectations of the followers, for, political events and revolutionary
practice had not coincided with the expectation derived from the Marxist
ideals.
Marcuse claimed that the modern world had brought
into existence a ‘new sensibility,’ with its demand for aesthetically
satisfying forms of immediate experience and its refusal to participate in
consumer society. It represented a significant new political force in the
world. The social change is necessary to accommodate the ‘new sensibility.’
Adorno in particular was uncompromising in his opposition to the idea that
philosophy should consist of a closed system of interconnected propositions
that rested on a purportedly firm foundation and claimed universal validity.
Jürgen Habermas, have tried to develop further some of the central components
of critical theory. In the second generation of critical theorists a return to
the kind of Neo-Kantian philosophy is witnessed. In the work of Habermas we
find the Kantian themes of finding a fixed universal framework for theorizing,
giving firm foundations for knowledge claims of various sorts, and
investigating the conditions of the possibility of various human activities.
The critical theroists had tried to make Marxism more viable and suited to
their own time. Especially Habermas tried to revise and reformulate Marxist
tradition. His project had a radical democratic character looking forward to
expand the sphere of freedom and aiming at harmony between theory and practice.
For him knowledge is historically rooted and interest bound. His theory of
communication claims that all speech is oriented towards the idea of genuine
consensus. In all, Critical method had contributed to philosophy in its
criticism of positivism and its demand that social theory be reflective. (Geuss
1998)
4.13 KEY WORDS
Instrumental Reason
: Rationality of humans defined
only in terms of domination and control of objects of nature, especially in
science.
Discourse ethics :
is communicative ethics where the norms are deliberated in the society and
validated.
Communicative Action : Habermasian theory of ideals with due emphasis on
practices being deliberated in ideal speech situations with speech acts.
.
UNIT 1 PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD: WESTERN AND
INDIAN
Contents
1.0 Objectives
1.1 Introduction
1.2 Phenomenology
in Philosophy
1.3 Phenomenology
as a method
1.4 Phenomenological
Analysis of Knowledge
1.5 Phenomenological
Reduction
1.6 Husserl’s
Triad: Ego, Cogito, Cogitata
1.7 Intentionality
1.8 Understanding
‘Consciousness’
1.9 Phenomenological
Method in Indian Tradition
1.10 Phenomenological
Method in Religion
1.11 Let us
Sum up
1.12 Key
Words
1.13 Further
Readings and References
1.0 OBJECTIVES
• To
expose to the students the phenomenology in both Western and Indian traditions
• To
illustrate the method used in philosophical systems concerning the human
subjectivity and consciousness.
1.1 INTRODUCTION
Edmund Husserl (1859-1938) was a German philosopher,
mathematician and physicist. His works are ‘Logical Investigation (1900),
Phenomenology and crisis of philosophy (1910), Ideas (1913), Cartecian
Meditation (1931), Philosophy and Crisis of European Man. Important contribution of Husserl is his
notions of ‘Intentionality, Noema and Noesis, Epoche, Life-world. His
phenomenology revolutionized philosophy. We understand the reality from our own
experience. Continental philosophy and hermeneutics evolved from phenomenology.
Understanding reality as a method in philosophy is phenomenological. There are
two features of phenomenology. First is all knowledge about reality or world
must be the last analysis with our highly personal experience. This brings in
the question of whether there is objective knowledge possible at all. Secondly,
Phenomenology is concerned with meaning or perspective I have on objects.
1.2 PHENOMENOLOGY IN PHILOSOPHY
Phenomenology is a study of ‘appearances’ as they
are experienced in one’s subjectivity. It is the study of structure of
consciousness which are common to all consciousness. It examines the way in
which phenomenology constituted “in” or
by” consciousness. Phenomenology is cognitive approach to the field of
studying aiming at rigorous and interpersonal knowledge by way of describing the
intentional act and intended object.
Hume used ‘phenomenologism,’ to mean it as only impression. Husserl uses
it differently. Kant used phenomenon and neumena as opposite in their
conception, former meaning ‘things as it appears’ and the latter to mean ‘things
as it is.’ Husserl’s usage was little closer to Kant yet different. Hegel also
used this term, phenomenology. His famous book phenomenology of spirit, clearly
shows that Hegelian notion is different in understanding although he used
Kantian terminology. Bentan influenced Husserl by his, what is known as,
descriptive psychology. He also used the word phenomenology he come closer to
Husserl. From the question of being, as
in metaphysics, phenomenology moved to the concern of ‘meaningfulness of reality.’
The terms phenomenon and phenomenology derive from the Greek for “appearance”.
Phenomenon refers to a thing or event that appears to human consciousness.
Phenomenology, thus, is the study of manifestations. Edmund Husserl believed
that as far as our knowledge of the world goes, all we can know is phenomena.
Husserl agreed with Descartes that the one thing we can be certain of is our
own conscious awareness.
1.3 PHENOMENOLOGY AS A METHOD
For Husserl European science in particular and
Western society in general had lost direction. From the time of enlightenment,
reason had increasingly bifurcated from man’s essential, ‘transcendental’,
identity. He was convinced that we should return to ‘things themselves’. The
method of approach he advocated for the attainment of these ends is called
phenomenology. In his phenomenological
method, Husserl succeeded in relocating reason as an intergral, a priori,
faculty of human consciousness. He
allows human consciousness to ‘intuit’ its own essence. For Descartes, what one
can be certain about existence is one’s own conscious awareness. Husserl agrees
with this view of consciousness. He says, ‘if we want to build our conception
of reality on rock-solid foundations, that this is the place to start’. (Magee
1998, 211) As Descartes begins by doubting everything but not doubting itself,
Husserl believes that the study of mind should begin by setting aside all that
is not given in consciousness: ‘all that does not belong e the mental state of
the subject’. (Scruton 1994, 139)
The method Husserl introduces for this analysis or
examination of things as they appear to our consciousness is called
‘phenomenology’. Husserl believes that the first step towards any attempt to
understand the theoretical problems which he confronts have to appropriate
access to phenomena themselves. Phenomenology thus evolves as a method of
approaching phenomena in their pure state. Phenomena, for Husserl, is anything,
imagined or objectively existing, ideal or real, that presents itself in any
away to individual consciousness. Husserl’s aim is to develop a method that
will not falsify these phenomena, but will allow them to be described as they
appear – as things themselves. Thus, when Husserl recommends the return to
things themselves, what he is recommending is a return to an analysis of things
as they appear to consciousness. Husserl thought that all sciences had evolved
randomly and were made up of a combination of empirical act and theoretical
supposition. Theoretically this hotchpotch was unacceptable: what was required
was a clear account of the nature and the theories which were deemed central to
scientific investigation. What was needed was a new method which could clearly
identify the metaphysical presuppositions inherent in the sciences.
1.4 PHENOMENOLOGICAL ANALYSIS OF KNOWLEDGE
Philosophy is more a method than a preoccupation
with knowing the reality. Epistemology is the study of the method of
knowing. The word epistemology comes
from two Greek words, namely, ‘episteme’ (knowledge) and ‘logos’ (science);
that is to say, it is the science of the being as the knowing, or the science
of human mind with respect to its aspect of knowing. In the past, it was called
Noetics, Gnoseology, Higher Logic, Material Logic, Critical Logic, Applied
Logic, and so on. Epistemology covers a
wider spectrum of themes. Apart from
laying the standards of truth, it treats the structure and the conditionings of
the knowing mind, the very process of cognition, the accompanying states of
mind, the role of sense organs in the cognitive process, the nature and
limitations of human knowledge, etc. When people ordinarily say that they know
something, most often, what they mean is that they believe, think, hope, opine,
doubt or wish something. However, when a philosopher says he knows something,
he means that he knows that thing beyond any doubt, with full certitude borne
out of a thorough scientific investigation. Normally we say that knowing is an
exclusive activity of human beings and inanimate things do not know. Although animals
possess some ‘intelligence’, we say it is mere instinctual responses or
conditions. Only humans have reason and
deliberate activity of knowing. In knowing we create a sort of mental
representation of a thing in the mind. A thing is said to be having a twofold
existence, within and without the mind.
Husserl dedicated himself to a search for the very
foundation of human knowledge. His first passion had been mathematics and he
became gripped by a vision of a philosophy that provided the certainty found in
mathematics. He wanted to create a philosophy that was a "rigorous
science". Yet his focus was not on the so-called "objective"
truths of empirical science, but on the "subjective" process of human
thinking; not on so-called "facts" but on "phenomena",
things as they appear to the mind.
For Husserl, all genuine knowledge rested on inner
evidence. Knowledge, in the strictest sense, means it is inwardly evident that
something is the case. Human acts must be fulfilling intuitions. In order to
grasp this ‘inner evidence’, it is necessary to ‘bracket’ all that is
inessential so that the essences of phenomena can speak for themselves. In
order to grasp this ‘inner evidence’, says Husserl, it is necessary to
‘bracket’ all that is inessential so that the essence of phenomena can speak
for itself. For Husserl the study of mind begins by setting aside all that is
not given in consciousness. It begins by
stripping our perceptions down to their simplest forms, shedding all our layers
of habit and assumption. Husserl calls this kind of perception “bracketing”.
Since all we can know are things that appear to our consciousness, he said, let
us ignore the questions that we cannot answer and deal with those we can
answer. The human mind understands the world by bringing it under certain
concepts, and each concept presents an essence. These essences are not
discovered by scientific inquiry and experiment, but are revealed to
consciousness where they can be grasped by intuition. In order to grasp the
true essence of things themselves we must clear the mind of all the debris that
prevents intuition from forming. And it is only by “bracketing” all those
presuppositions and prejudices which clutter our minds that we can approach the
true essence of the object: that we can study what is left as an object of pure
inner awareness.
For Husserl, the ultimate truth is that all we can
know for certain is that we have pure consciousness. All objects and acts that
appear to consciousness must be treated with circumspection: they must be kept
under constant review. Before feelings, imaginings, fears, doubts, and even
thought itself, there is pure consciousness – the transcendental ego. Thus,
while Husserl seems to echo Descartes, in effect he goes beyond the cogito. For
Descartes the only thing we can know with any certainty is that we are thinking
things – “I think, therefore I am”. For Husserl, it is more the case that “I
am, therefore I think”. Pure consciousness can be grasped by thought, but it is
not synonymous with thought. For Husserl, in order to think, first we must be –
we must have consciousness. (H. Spielberg "The Phenomenological
Movement" Vol. 1 1865, pp.76-82.)
1.5 PHENOMENOLOGICAL REDUCTION
Phenomenological reduction, according to Husserl’s
teachings, is the exclusion from consideration of everything. It is
transcendent and anything else derived via scientific or logical inference. A
phenomenologist would consider only what was immediately presented to
consciousness. For Jean-Paul Sartre, what one suggested what one know of a
person or item are all that one can evaluate. An object, even a person, is only
what one sees and experiences of that object. The rest, Husserl suggested, was
“bracketed out” from judgment. Husserl referred to this suspension of judgment
as epoché. As an example, via this theory, a colour seen by one individual is
known only to and by that one person. Measuring it scientifically, comparing to
other colours, et cetera, do not truly change that what the individual sees is
the only thing consciousness comprehends. The colour experienced is the “pure
phenomena”, the scientific data are held in suspension, or epoché. Only the
phenomenological knowledge is certain, and then only to the individual.
Eidetic reduction is the abstraction of essences.
The essence abstracted via eidetic reduction is the intelligible structure of
the phenomena found in consciousness. The goal is to find the basic components
of a phenomena. For example, a chair might include the colour, the materials
used, and the shapes present in the structure. We apply basic, Platonic forms
to all phenomena, according to Husserl. These basics allow us to communicate
and describe a phenomena with some accuracy, though this lessens the original
phenomena in some manner. Returning to the example of colour, one knows there
are component colours. If one thinks too much about the mixture of colours, the
colour viewed is devalued. Green is green, according to Husserl, not a mixture
of blue and yellow subtractive. The scientific knowledge of colour is the universal
form: there are agreed upon mathematical representations of colour. Still,
colour is a personal and subjective phenomena, further complicated by
differences in human senses, such as colour blindness.
Husserl was unable to come out of this transcendental
suspension. The harmless “bracketing” of commonsense realities became the
metaphysical thesis that they can have none but an “intentional” existence in
and for consciousness. Husserl does not see that we cannot suspend a belief if
the belief suspended is meaningless.
(Findlay, Encyclopedia of Western Philosophy, 145)
1.6 HUSSERL’S TRIAD: EGO, COGITO, COGITATA
What a phenomenologist considers important is that
which can be experienced via the human senses. After reduction and abstraction,
what remains is what an individual knows, regardless of the scientific or
transcendental data. After removing the transcendental and the scientific, what
remains is the Phenomenological Residue of the phenomena. This residue exists
in three forms: ego, cogito, and cogitata. Phenomenological Ego is the stream
of consciousness in which one acquires meaning and reality from the surrounding
environment. Husserl considered it a great mystery and wonder that a group of
beings was aware of their existence, in effect human consciousness is the
phenomenological result of introspection. By observing that “I can touch and
see my being,” we recognize that we exist. The science proving we exist is not
of value to human consciousness. The ego is always present, or nothing exists for
the individual. Cogito or cogitations comprise all the acts of consciousness,
including doubting, understanding, affirming, denying, etc. The ego exists only
as a result of these cogitations and these cogitations continue only as long as
we are self-aware. Cogitata are the subjects of thought or objects of
consideration. One cannot deny or understand nothing — something must be under
consideration for thought to occur. In the presence of nothing, there is no
person, no individual.
1.7 INTENTIONALITY
It comes from two word “in + tendare” ‘in’ means
towards. ‘Tendare’ means tending, tending towards. Husserl did not use it for
first time but Avicena (Islamic) used this word and later on developed by
scholastic philosophers. Intentionality is the power and the vitality of
consciousness. He says physical objects have no intentionality. Only mental
objects have intentionality. Physical objects have capacity to tend to its
objects. Intentionality is stereological towards objects. Intentionality has
direction in a way, object-orientedness. Physical objects are not
oriented. Consciousness always refers to
something. Consciousness is always conscious ‘of’ something. Consciousness must
have an object always. He says “ego cogito cogitatum” I think something. So far
philosophers said only I think but Husserl told that “I always think
something.” What is that something is a different question altogether, but
thinking is always about something. Consciousness is co-relational, not just
relational. Descartes theory of consciousness is called container theory of
consciousness as he says that consciousness is simply reflection of objects.
Kant also says that mind has a role to play. Co-relational means it is
reference theory of consciousness. For Husserl my mind is not simply
reflecting.
Meaning, says Husserl, is neither in the mind, nor
in the world alone, rather it is discovered by the a priori modes of
intentionality. These intentional modes fall into three categories –
perception, imagination, and signification. Intentionality is like a screen
between consciousness and the world onto which objects and acts are projected.
Without the screen objects and acts would not exist. Intentionality, then is a
conduit, a channel, between consciousness and phenomena. Consciousness itself
cannot be grasped as itself because it is intentional: it is always directed
towards that which is not consciousness: it is always looking away from itself.
It is only by an analysis of intentionality that consciousness itself can be
discovered. Thus, when we peel away the encrustaceans of preconditioning not
only can we intuit the essence of things themselves but also the essence of
consciousness – pure consciousness. To examine consciousness, we need to
bracket out all objects and facts. What remains is “the transcendental ego”,
which, for Husserl, is pure being - Absolute Being. It is important to realise
that Husserl does not deny that the real world exists; rather that it is only
realisable in virtue of the transcendental ego. Without pure consciousness,
nothing is possible. Pure consciousness is before all acts and objects. It is
only through pure consciousness that all other entities are known; and they are
known as entities that appear in consciousness.
For Husserl the world and the entire filed of
objectivities would appear before us as being correlated with consciousness.
Transcendental consciousness ‘constitutes’ the world. In spite of his insistence on methodological
devices for phenomenology, Husserl’s followers and the philosophical scholarship
have not been able to see their relevance for a phenomenological way of doing
philosophy. H.L. van breda, Eugine Fink, J.N. Findlay, H. Spiegelberg and
Merleau-Ponty are unanimous on the dubious philosophical value of these
devices. (Rafy, 2010)
1.8 UNDERSTANDING ‘CONSCIOUSNESS’
Husserl’s view on the self is understood from the
issues concerning the unity of consciousness. Hume says, “There are some
philosophers, who imagine we are every moment intimately conscious of what we
call our SELF; that we feel its existence and its continuance in existence….
For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call myself, I always
stumble on some particular perception or other, or heat or cold, light or
shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I never can catch myself at any time
without a perception, and never can observe anything but the perception.”(Hume
1978, 251-2). Reflection does not reveal a continuously existing self. It is a
constantly changing stream of mental states. There is no impression of self.
The idea or concept of self that we have of ourselves is problematic. For Hume,
there are two problems of conscious unity: firstly, synchronic unity of
consciousness and the distinction between subjects of experience; secondly,
diachronic unity.
Kantian understanding agrees at one level with Hume
on the question of self-awareness but goes in disagreement concerning the
legitimacy of the concept of the self. The diverse experiences are unified by
the self, as Kant says, “The thought that these representations given in
intuition all together belong to me means, accordingly, the same as that I
unite them in a self-consciousness, or at least can unite them therein… for
otherwise I would have as multicoloured, diverse a self as I have
representations of which I am conscious.” (Kant 1929, sec. B143). Kant brings
in the notion of the self as unifier of experience. For him, it is legitimate
to appeal to an ‘I’ that unifies experience since such a thing is precisely a
condition of the possibility of experience. Without such a unifying self,
experience would not be possible. The I, for Kant is transcendental. It is
brought into the account as a condition of the possibility of experience.
Husserl claims that the self is experienced indirect
intuition. He writes, “I exist for myself and am constantly given to myself, by
experiential evidence, as ‘I myself.’ This is true of the transcendental ego
and, correspondingly, of the psychologically pure ego; it is true, moreover,
with respect to any sense of the word ego.” (Husserl 1960, sec. 33). For Kant
the ‘I’ has a role in structuring experience but not given itself in
experience. For Husserl the ‘I’ plays this structuring role and is also given
in inner experience. The ego appears but not as (part of) a mental process.
It’s presence is continual and unchanging. Husserl says that it is, “a
transcendency within immanency” (Husserl 1982, sec. 57). It is immanent in that
it is on the subject side of experience; It is transcendent in that it is not
an experience (or part of one).
Sartre understands that consciousness is empty and
denies not only of sensory qualities but also our experiential awareness of an
ego within consciousness. Sartre denies that the ego is given in pre-reflective
experience, either in the content of experience (as an object) or as a
structural feature of the experience itself (as a subject). As he puts it,
“while I was reading, there was consciousness of the book, of the heroes of the
novel, but the ‘I’ was not inhabiting this consciousness. It was only
consciousness of the object and non-positional consciousness of itself.”
(Sartre 1960, 46-7). Again, “When I run after a streetcar, when I look at the
time, when I am absorbed in contemplating a portrait, there is no I.” (Sartre
1960, 48-9). For him, the self can appear to consciousness, but it is
paradoxically experienced as something outside of, transcendent to,
consciousness. With respect to unreflective consciousness, however, Sartre
denies self-awareness. Sartre also denies that the ego is required to
synthesise, or unite, one’s various experiences. Rather, as he sees it, the
unity of consciousness is achieved via the objects of experience, and via the
temporal structure of experience.
1.9 PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD IN INDIAN
TRADITION
All classical Indian schools speak of consciousness,
its intrinsic nature, its place in the causal processes, its relations to
objects in the world, and the possibilities. Accordingly their epistemological
conceptions are shaped by their positions on consciousness. Key issues are
whether it has forms of its own or assume content with reference to objects,
its relation to objects in the world. Madhyamikas have anti-theoretical notion
on it. Nyaya and Mimamsa take world-oriented theories, while Advaita vedanta
speak of self as consciousness in a spiritual and mystical sense. Advaita is
emphatic about the world-transcendent nature of consciousness. The only content
of it is self-aware consciousness itself.
The worldly content is viewed as an illusion and a deformation, a falling
away from being conscious in itself. The
relation is explained this way: With regard to the world, uninvolved witnessing
is upheld as the state the least estranged from what consciousness is in
itself. Samkhya and Yoga prefer a dualistic view of consciousness with regard
to nature of it. The world is contrary to the true nature of consciousness.
They are separate realities. It is problematic how they are related at all.
Nature ranges without break from luminous and malleable mentality to gross material
elements. In this the mind is viewed as capable of presenting to the witnessing
person of things that are continuous with the things represented. (Phillips
1998).
Yogacara deployed arguments similar to
epistemological idealists. Theirs were also compared to Kant as held by Western
scholars. Some even think that these Buddhist thinking is very closer to
Husserl’s phenomenology. There are lots of similarities between what is known
as Husserl’s description of noesis and noema, and Buddhist analysis of the grahaka
and grahya. Husserl’s noesis is the
consciousness projecting its cognitive field. Yogacara's grahaka is a similar
to noesis as a cognitive grasper. Noema of western phenomenological tradition,
which is understood as the constructed cognitive object, is similar to the
cognitive grasped, grahya of the Buddhist tradition.
Husserl did play down the notions of causality.
Yogacara developed complex systematic causal theories. These theories were
considered as of great importance to Yogacara. In western tradition the
ontological realm was afforded at least sufficient to acknowledge its existence
in their philosophical enquiry method. Whereas for yogacara was critical of
that particular motive in all its manifestations. Yogacara is a type of
epistemological idealism. The purpose of its arguments was not to produce an
ontological theory of reality. They insisted on shifting one’s attention to the
epistemological and psychological conditions of human cognitive activities that
compel us to construct and attach to ontological theories. From being
epistemological idealists they could extend their investigations to be critical
realists.
Yogacara has the doctrine of types of consciousness
(manovijnana)- visual, auditory, etc. Each consciousness is produced by the
contact between its specific sense organ and a corresponding object.
Consciousness depends on sensation.
Enlightenment consists in bringing consciousness to an end, replacing
with enlightened cognitive abilities (jnana). When consciousness ends, true knowledge
begins. (Lusthaus, 1998)
1.10 PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD IN RELIGION
What is called the phenomenology of religion is a
descriptive approach to the philosophy of religion. Meaning and understanding
of what is religion is a primary issue in it. From the existing divergent
beliefs and practices among various religions, the quest for the essence of
religion is sought here. With an existential orientation, the concern is more
towards our own mode of being in the world than about the question of ultimate
being. So the issue is what it means to be religious with the faith and beliefs
one has. From phenomenological perspective, philosophy of religion is merely a
normative enterprise reflecting on the truth of religious beliefs with proofs
and arguments for and against. Phenomenology of religion brackets such concerns
and holds that religion is an observable phenomenon of human life. To understand better what is religion is to
give a descriptive analyses of that aspect of human experience and to give us
deeper insight into the structures and functions of these widespread human
activities. Phenomenologist approaches religion as a matter of belief and
focuses attention of the essence or the common nature of religions.
For Kant, we can set forth the basic structures of
our experience of the world although there can be metaphysical disputes about
what the world really is. So, the subject matter is phenomenal rather than
noumenal. In Husserlean method transcends the natural attitude by moving from
fact to essence and by bracketing questions about the reality of the world as
distinct from the mode of its givenness in experience (the epoche). Kierkegaard
says that reflection always emerge from within the concrete situatedness of
human existence. It clarifies the possibilities that confront us.
Phenomenological method in religion presupposes that theoretical reason cannot
settle metaphysical disputes in all its modes and criticizes traditional method
of philosophy of religion as engaging in unwarranted speculation on things that
are undecidables. Even the debates in theology become theoretician’s luxury in
a realm of abstraction that is least bothered about the living God and the
concrete concerns and inescapable choices of existing individuals.
From the objective question of what is religion?
God? and so on, the phenomenological concern is towards What would it mean to
be religious distinct from being irreligious?
Phenomenological method here is looking more for meanings than facts;
meanings as living; looking for what happens rather than what happened. As Phenomenology addresses itself to modes of
our experience the focus is not just the subjective side of religion but on the
‘object’ of religious experience. In this sense, the concept of God or gods,
for instance, not appropriate for religious ‘objects’ as the Buddha nature.
This ‘Buddhahood’ is the being of all things and yet anatta, non-substance or
no-self. Again, the highest experience of God or Brahman or Allah etc., is
beyond the structure of subject-object experience. Hence the terms like
‘sacred’ ‘holy’ ‘divine’ ‘power’ ‘other’ become generic names for the ‘object’
of religion. Van der Leeuw stresses its
remoteness. However frequently one encounters it, it never becomes usual or
familiar, but remains a ‘highly exceptional
and extremely dangerous "Other"’ ([1933] 1963 (1): 24). Accordingly,
encounters with the sacred are accompanied by amazement, fear, and especially
awe. Rudolf Otto’s earlier study, The Idea of the Holy (1917), defines the holy
as the mysterium tremendum et fascinans (overwhelming and fascinating mystery).
The holy as mysterious is the ‘object’ of religion which is non-rational or
ineffable in the sense of exceeding our conceptual apprehension. Calling it as
mysterium tremendum evokes fear and dread and designates the sacred as wholly
other. Yet as fascinans, it is uniquesly attractive and fascinating. (Westphal,
1998)
1.11 LET US
SUM UP
Phenomenology is not a unified doctrine as its main
proponents - Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre and Merleau-Ponty - interpret it
differently. Phenomenology is a method of philosophical investigation which
results in a radical ontological revision of Cartesian Dualism. In
phenomenology consciousness is intentional and directed onto objects.
Phenomenologists interpret the intentionality to mean that subjects and objects
are essentially interrelated. All consciousness is essentially consciousness of
objects and all objects are essentially, if not explicitly, objects of
consciousness.
As a method in arriving at knowledge, especially in
dealing with research methodology in philosophy, phenomenology has a lot to
contribute. Phenomenological method has a purpose of being descriptive and
presuppositionless. It is descriptive of one’s experience of the world by
putting aside assumptions about the world’s existence and character. And
secondly, one seeks to describe particular, concrete phenomena. Phenomena are
not contents of the mind; they all involve an experiencing subject and an
experienced object. Phenomenological description aims to make explicit
essential features implicit in the ‘lived-world’ - the world as we act in it
prior to any theorizing about it. The phenomenological method reveals that
practical knowledge is prior to propositional knowledge - knowing that arises from
knowing how.
As being presuppositionless it scrutinizes
scientific and philosophical theories.
The phenomenological reduction is as called by Husserl ‘bracketing’ or
‘the epoché’. It is to bring to our attention the realm of phenomena, the
‘lived-world’, the world as we experience it. Basic aim of phenomenological
method is to explore how the world appears with a view to finding the
experiential basis for, and meaning of, our belief that the world exists
independently of our experience of it. Phenomena are our experiences of the
world. One needs to remain neutral concerning the ontological status of that
‘world’. Phenomenological description can avoid theoretical assumption of
reality. While theoretical entities may have a place in the natural sciences,
they have no legitimate place in philosophical enquiry. Philosophy should not
take scientific realism for granted.
1.12 KEY WORDS
Phenomenology:
It is a study of ‘appearances’ as they are experienced in one’s
subjectivity.
Bracketing (epoche): For Husserl the study of mind
begins by setting aside all that is not given in consciousness. It begins by stripping our perceptions down
to their simplest forms, shedding all our layers of habit and assumption.
Husserl calls this kind of perception “bracketing”.
Phenomenological reduction: According to Husserl it is the exclusion from
consideration of everything. It is transcendent and anything else derived via
scientific or logical inference.
Cogito or cogitations: It comprises all the acts of
consciousness, including doubting, understanding, affirming, denying, etc.
Cogitata: They are the subjects of thought or
objects of consideration. One cannot deny or understand nothing — something
must be under consideration for thought to occur. In the presence of nothing,
there is no person, no individual.
Intentionality: It is the power and the vitality of
consciousness. Physical objects have no intentionality. Only mental objects
have intentionality.
UNIT 2 ANALYTICAL METHOD:
WESTERN AND INDIAN
Contents
2.0 Objectives
2.1 Introduction
2.2 Analysis
in History of Philosophy
2.3 Conceptual
Analysis
2.4 Analysis
as a Method
2.5 Analysis
in Logical Atomism and Logical Positivism
2.6 Analytic
Method in Ethics
2.7 Language
Analysis
2.8 Quine’s
Analytical Method
2.9 Analysis
in Indian Traditions
2.10 Let us
Sum up
2.11 Key
Words
2.12 Further
Readings and References
2.0 OBJECTIVES
• To
introduce to the students philosophical discussions on meaningfulness of word,
sentence in language used.
• To
give a overall picture of analytical tradition both in West and India on the
question of language and reality.
• To
enable students to cull out from the philosophies of language analytical method
used in sorting out philosophical problems.
2.1 INTRODUCTION
Generally any philosophical analysis is a method of
inquiry. Analysis is normally understood
as assessing complex systems through simpler elements. In philosophical
analysis we do seek the complex thought pattern by breaking them into simpler
components. Analytic philosophy was a leading philosophical tradition and a
dominant branch of philosophy in the West in 20th century. Having emerged and
dominated the English speaking world for decades analytical tradition steadily
grew to influence the continental philosophy.
From the beginning of Indian philosophical tradition there had been
issues related to meaning of terms, sentences and the meaningfulness of
language. This we may consider in par
with the 20th century discussion in the West on language and reality.
2.2 ANALYSIS IN HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY
Analytical method has a long history in philosophy,
although it became prominent at the start of the twentieth century. In
classical Greek, the term ‘analysis’ denoted the activity of taking something
apart and became a model for explanations of complex structures in reference to
parts. In Descartes, the idea of analysis reappeared with the reference to
identify the simple natures as characteristic of one’s subject-matter.
(Arnauld, A.; Descartes, R.). In John Locke’s account of complex ideas in terms
of their constituent simple ideas the analysis found a place. Moving from the
Cartesian analysis of ‘ideas’ to the analysis of our capacities for
understanding and judgement, Kant’s position is ‘Transcendental Analytic.’ In the further development of idealist
tradition, we find in Hegel a shift from the method of analysis to the method
of dialectic. (Baldwin 1998)
G. E. Moore appropriately calls for a return to the
method of analysis breaking the idealistic trend of dialectics. He maintained that ‘a thing becomes
intelligible first when it is analysed into its constituent concepts’ (Moore
1899: 182). Moorean conception of analysis inspired Russell in his analytical
programme. Logical positivists developed the method further in their
anti-metaphysical project. Russell’s development of logical theory paved a way
for analysis as legitimate philosophical inquiry. Expanding the philosophical
inquiries beyond the logical positivist’s position, analytical philosophy included
the analysis of structures of language and thought. From the conception of
linguistic analysis the central concern of analytical philosophy became
language and meaning. Frege and Quine forwarded arguments for and against the
methods of analysis. Brentano’s approach to psychology was explicitly
analytical, which enables us to understand Husserl’s programme of
phenomenological analysis. American pragmatist, C.S. Peirce wrote that ‘the
only thing I have striven to do in philosophy has been to analyse sundry
concepts with exactitude’ (Passmore [1957] 1968: 104).
By 1945 most analytical philosophers had abandoned
any commitment to simple meanings and basic certainties, and that the
positivist thesis that philosophy could only be analytical philosophy was also
soon rejected. They rested only on the assumption that methods of analysis can
clarify conceptual and epistemological relationships that would contribute to
dissipation of philosophical problems. Quine questioned the assumption that
there is a clear distinction (the ‘analytic/synthetic’ distinction) between
logic and other disciplines and the assumption that there is a single chain of
justification from observation to more speculative claims about the world
(Quine 1953). For him we find only a complex network of interdependent
relationships and our understanding of each other, and in particular of each
other’s utterances, is generally underdetermined by our observations of each
other. Quine earlier pointed to the holistic structure of our language and beliefs.
Rorty viewed that Quine’s writings signaled the end of analytical philosophy
(Rorty 1980). Yet, analytical philosophy still survives by retreating to the
pre-positivist position of analysis as an ingredient of philosophical inquiry,
involving inference and justification that connect concepts, beliefs and
statements. Analytical philosophy made a remarkable expansion, both
geographically and disciplinary, with the acceptance and use of its methods in
outside Europe and in areas of philosophy such as ancient philosophy and
Marxism. (Baldwin 1998).
Recently analytical philosophy turned its attention
to philosophy of religion. Early thinkers had anti-metaphysical trend where
religious claims were considered as unverifiable or as part of a language game.
After 1950s Plantinga contributed to epistemology of religion and Swinburne has
worked extensively in natural theology. Analytical tradition now covers range
of topics from traditional theistic concerns to objections to theism. (Wehinger
2010)
2.3 CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS
The theory of conceptual analysis holds that
concepts are the fundamental objects of philosophical inquiry. Accordingly,
insights into conceptual contents are expressed in necessary ‘conceptual
truths’ (analytic propositions) which could be obtained by two methods: (1)
direct a priori definition of concepts; (2) indirect ’transcendental’
argumentation. John Locke’s doctrines of general ideas and definitions had an
element of analysis in decompositions of complex general ideas into sets of
simple ideas. Further analysis had its foot in Locke’s distinction between
‘trifling’ and ‘instructive,’ universally certain propositions and in his
distinction between ‘intuitive’ and ‘demonstrative’ knowledge. In his Critique
of Pure Reason, Kant makes three crucial sets of distinctions; between
‘analytic’ and ’synthetic’ propositions, between a priori (necessary,
experience-independent) and a posteriori (contingent, experience-dependent)
truths, between proofs by empirical methods and ’transcendental’ proofs. (Hanna
1998)
2.4 ANALYSIS AS A METHOD
Explanation of a whole by referring to its parts,
becomes a gist of analysis. Although in physical science the decomposition of a
whole into its parts is well understood, analysis in philosophy needs certain
clarification. In logical analysis the inferential significance of a statement
in its logical form depends on the simple logical constants in the statement.
Logical analysis of a statement can lead one to discern the presence of logical
constants which are not apparent in the surface structure of the statement. For
instance, in Russell’s famous illustration, “The present King of France is
bald.” For Russell, a statement’s logical analysis revealed the ‘constituents’
of the proposition expressed by the statement. Complex claims to knowledge are
justified by reference to simpler items of evidence. In empiricist tradition, all evidence is
perceptual evidence. Analysis of perceptual evidence unravels the complexity of
beliefs. Phenomenological analyses are not mere introspective descriptions of
appearance but are meant to bring out the priorities within different modes of
consciousness. (Baldwin 1998).
Russell develops his theory of descriptions into a
theory of ‘logical fictions.’ It implies that our ontological commitments are
less extensive than it is supposed. For
both Moore and Russell philosophy is not just analysis. Wittgenstein brought
out the paradigmatic exercise in logical analysis with assumption that ‘A proposition has one and only one complete
analysis’ (Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus 1922: 3.25). From the Vienna circle
the positivists analysis rested on the beliefs that ‘what is left over for
philosophy… is only a method: the method of logical analysis’ (Carnap 1932:
77). For them the proper task of the philosopher is to engage in
logico-epistemological analysis. It
clarifies the questions about the world with the answers based on scientific
observation and experiment. In the explicitly anti-metaphysical contexts of logical
positivism we find the transition from ‘philosophical analysis’ to ‘analytical
philosophy.’ The former is conceived of as an important method of inquiry while
the latter restricts genuine philosophy to analysis. (Baldwin 1998).
Analytic method in philosophy has a diverse concerns
from logic, epistemology and language.
The developments within analytic tradition show this. Concerns of the
analytic philosophers ranges from aesthetics to ethics to history of
philosophy. There is no defiition in terms of a certain set of doctrines or
method for analytical philosophy. From the early days of analytical tradition
there was no shared methodological approach among philosophers. Even after the
linguistic turn there was no methodological constraint on the philosophers to
adopt. In post-Quinean period we find concerns of analytical traditon on
metaphysics, mind, religion, etc. Amidst the diversity of doctirne and methods
analytical philosophy is a method of philosophizing. It emphasized argument,
rationality and sought clarity. (Wehinger 2010)
Method in
Conceptual Analysis
In any conceptual analysis, the theory is as
follows: A concept is a general content possessing intrinsic, individuating
structures and relations (an intension), and having a corresponding application
either to sets of actual or possible objects (an extension), or to other
concepts. Secondly, a concept is the meaning of a predicate-expression; and all
such words have meanings only in the context of whole sentences used (first and
foremost) in making statements in ordinary discourse. Thirdly, every true
proposition expressing conceptual interconnections is necessary and analytic.
Fourthly, purely conceptual inquiry produces important a priori knowledge. This
knowledge is expressed in analytic propositions known to be true either by (a)
direct definitional analysis of conceptual contents, or by (b) indirect
‘transcendental’ arguments. Fifthly, all fundamental philosophical errors arise
from misunderstandings of concepts, and can be corrected only by proper
conceptual analyses. Therefore from the above understanding on the concept and
knowledge, concepts are understood as playing a role as universals. They
ontologically depend upon ordinary language and not otherworldly. Concepts have
necessary relations to one another. Concepts govern the ways we think about all
things and other concepts. Thus not only all philosophical truths, but also all
philosophical errors, are conceptual. The two methods of conceptual analysis -
definitional and transcendental - must be employed not merely as means of
philosophical insight but also for the unmasking and diagnosis of conceptual
confusions. (Hanna 1998)
2.5 ANALYSIS IN LOGICAL ATOMISM AND LOGICAL
POSITIVISM
In the beginning of 20th century G.E. Moore and
Betrand Russell opposed the British idealism. Moore’s A Refutation of Idealism
(1903) and Russell’s (along with A.N. Whitehead) Principia Mathematica became
influential for analytical method. It aimed at reconstructing ambiguous or
misguiding terms of our language by means of the ideal language of predicate
logic. It tried to develop a foundation that logic and mathematics could be
based on. Gottlob Frege’s logical tools were adopted well by Russell. (Wehinger
2010)
Logical positivist like Alfred Jules Ayer endorsed
the ideal of scientific knowledge. The goal was to reconstruct, on the basis of
empirical observation and by means of formal logic, our statements about the
world. The logical positivists dismissed as meaningless those statements for
which such a reconstruction was not possible and that were not tautologically
true. The logical positivists thus
embraced a verificationist criterion of meaning. Only verifiable statements can
be meaningful. (Wehinger 2010)
2.6 ANALYTIC METHOD IN ETHICS
Moral philosophy has traditionally been divided into
normative ethics and meta-ethics. Normative ethics concerns judgments about
what is good and how we should act. Meta-ethics, with which ’analytic ethics’
is typically identified, seeks to understand such judgments. The questions
before analytic ethics are: are they factual statements capable of being
literally true or false? Or are they commands or expressions of attitude,
capable only of greater or lesser appropriateness or efficacy? The former leads
to cognitivism where the focus is on the facts of moral judgments. The latter
leads to non-cognitivism. The cognitivists question whether they are discovered
from experience or they are like mathematical facts. The noncognitivists argue
that moral judgments are not fact-stating and that they are only signals of our
feelings or commitments, or are imperatives of conduct. Concerning the moral
judgments another question is whether they are subjective or objective.
Analytic ethics is concerned about the meaning of moral terms. It offers
specific insights into morality and contributes to our understanding of the
functions of thought and language.
(Railton 1998)
In ethics some like Hume, stressed the role of
sentiment and others like Kant stressed reason for the faculty involved in
moral judgments. Ordinary moral practice or the external force as a standard
for moral judgment was discussed. After analytical philosophy, especially after
G.E. Moore, questions of meaning got separated from substantive questions,
moral concepts discussed in non-moral terms (for example, ‘Good’ = ‘Conducive
to happiness’). Good cannot be analytically reduced to a natural property.
Logical positivists divided cognitively significant propositions into two
categories, the analytic, knowable a priori because tautological, and the
synthetic, knowable a posteriori by empirical means. Loyal to the positivist
bifurcation, A.J. Ayer (1936) concluded that moral judgments expressed not
cognitively significant propositions, but emotions. (Railton 1998)
2.7 LANGUAGE ANALYSIS
In post-world war period in the West, many did not
want to return directly to old-fashioned metaphysics. They extended the analytical techniques to
normative aspects of language. In Wittgenstein’s writings there was a hope to
end philosophical perplexities. In the
writings of Ryle, Austin, Strawson and other ‘ordinary language’ philosophers
there was still old metaphysical questions like status of the mind, appearances
and universals.
After 1960s Analytical philosophy was no longer
confined to the logico-epistemological analyses of Russell and the logical
positivists. It has a much broader concern with language. Russell, Moore and
early Ludwig Wittgenstein, thought that such logical or conceptual analysis—in
the sense of a reconstruction of language with the tools of logic—would
eventually yield the simple, unanalyzable building bricks of reality, a view
called logical atomism. Later this emphasis on conceptual analysis turned into
a move towards language as the primary object of enquiry. This linguistic turn
asserted that a philosophical explanation can only be achieved by way of an
analysis of language. (Wehinger 2010)
Frege’s sense/refernce distinction was significant
in this context. Frege’s philosophy of language was brought into the mainstream
of analytical philosophy through Carnap’s writings. Dummett’s claim that the
distinctive feature of analytical philosophy is the priority it assigns to the
philosophy of language. The sentences are true only in virtue of the
nonlinguistic thoughts they express. His ‘theory of meaning’ and of Donald
Davidson are to be seen against ‘theorizing’ of Wittgenstein’s later writings.
There are those who argue for the alternative priority of mind over language employ
the methods of logical and epistemological analysis characteristic of previous
analytical philosophers. They threatened to bring about the ‘end of analytical
philosophy.’ (Baldwin 1998)
Ordinary language philosophy emerged after the fall
of logical positivism. From the Moorean common sense approach towards
philosophical problems, which argued that the philosopher’s starting point had
to be the ordinary meaning of propositions, ordinary language philosopher
stressed the need for not replacing the meaning but to elucidate the ordinary
meaning of the statements in accordance with common sense. Later Wittgenstein’s
influence for the ordinary language movement is worth mentioning. He questioned
the idea of an ideal language in favour of a plurality of what he called
language games, each of which functions according to its own rules. He put the
linguistic turn of logical positivists into practice. He was convinced that
traditional philosophical problems arise only if we do not use words in
accordance with the rules of the corresponding language game. Accordingly, the
philosopher’s task was to cure such misuse of language. (Wehinger 2010)
2.8 WITTGENSTEIN AND ANALYTICAL METHOD
In his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, Wittgenstein
presents a logical atomist picture of reality and language. The world is full
of independent facts. Each is composed of some combination of simple objects.
Each object has a distinctive logical shape which fits it to combine only with
certain other objects. These objects are named by the basic elements of
language. Each name has the same logical shape. An elementary sentence is a
combination of names. If it is true it will be a picture of the isomorphic fact
formed by the combination of the named objects. Ordinary sentences are misleading
in their surface form. When analysed these would reveal the real complexity
implicit in them. These deep truths about the nature of reality cannot be
properly be said but can only be shown. The picture theory of meaning: In each
individual sentences, one needs to understand that each says one thing but is
essentially either true or false. The sentence is complex and has components
which represent elements of reality. The truth or falsity of the sentence then
depends on whether these elements are or are not assembled into a fact. When we
properly understand the nature of our language we see that we cannot formulate
the supposed sentences in the first place.
Picture Theory:
Picture theory is the earlier position of Wittgenstein. According to
this theory, the ontological structure of the world which is logical has its
parallel in the structure of the language. The names being basic constituents
of the propositions which are either true or false as expressed in the logic of
language have a correspondence to the structure of the world. That which can be
logically represented in the language is a possible state of affairs in the
world. The logical necessity of propositions determines the states of affairs
in the world.
Language Game: Language game theory is expressed in
the Investigations. The language game theory moves from the foundations of
logic to the nature of the world. The
shift therefore is from the limited understanding of language, language of the
natural sciences to the language of wider forms of life. It is no longer one
view of language rather languages within the language. A sentence / proposition
does presuppose a ‘language game’, but a language game will be only a small
segment of the whole of language. It is the use, employment of particular word in the given language game
gives rise to meaning. The language game theory therefore, is the understanding
that the language is determined by rules which are particular to the
form-of-life.
Later in his Philosophical Investigations,
Wittgenstein changes his previous position presenting language not as a fixed
and timeless framework but as an aspect of vulnerable and changeable human
life. He changed the idea that words name simple objects was incoherent, and
instead introduced the idea of ‘language games’. When a language is taught
words and actions are interwoven. To understand a word is to know how to use it
in everyday life. He abandoned also solipsism and favoured the view that there
are many selves, aware of and cooperating with each other in their shared
world.
In presenting the contrasting views in his earlier
and later writings, Wittgenstein contributed to analytical tradition that
philosophical puzzles often arise out of language. Philosophical insight is not
to be gained by constructing quasi-scientific theories of puzzling phenomena.
It is to be achieved by seeking to be intellectually honest. (Heal 1998)
2.8 QUINE’S
ANALYTICAL METHOD
Quine insisted upon a close connection or alliance
between philosophical views and those of the natural sciences. Philosophy is an
activity within nature wherein nature examines itself. Quine takes account of
the theoretical as well as the observational facets of science. The unit of
empirical significance is not simple impressions (ideas) or even isolated
individual observation sentences, but systems of beliefs. Quine proposes a new
conception of observation sentences, a naturalized account of our knowledge of
the external world, including a rejection of a priori knowledge. Quine confines
logic to first-order logic and clearly demarcates it from set theory and
mathematics. They are internal to our system of beliefs that make up the
natural sciences. The language of first-order logic serves as a canonical
notation in which to express our ontological commitments. Our ontological
commitments should be to those objects to which the best scientific theories
commit us.
The theory of reference is sharply demarcated from
the theory of meaning. Quine is the leading critic of notions from the theory
of meaning, arguing that attempts to make the distinction between merely
linguistic (analytic) truths and more substantive (synthetic) truths has
failed. They do not meet the standards of precision which scientific and
philosophical theories adhere to and which are adhered to in the theory of
reference. He explores the limits of an empirical theory of language and offers
a thesis of the indeterminacy of translation as further criticism of the theory
of meaning. The picture theory of meaning: In each individual sentences, one
needs to understand that each says one thing but is essentially either true or
false. The sentence is complex and has components which represent elements of
reality. The truth or falsity of the sentence then depends on whether these
elements are or are not assembled into a fact. When we properly understand the
nature of our language we see that we cannot formulate the supposed sentences
in the first place. (Orenstein 1998)
Quine challenged the logical positivists’
distinction between analytic and synthetic truths and the verification of
scientific claims. He rejected the method of conceptual analysis. He proposed a
holistic account of meaning. Meaning of a statement cannot be fixed once and
for. It depends on the relation it has with other statements within a language.
Through his ontological relativity, he claimed that reference is inscrutable.
2.9 ANALYSIS IN INDIAN TRADITIONS
From the ancient Vedic period onwards debates on
language and linguistic theories has received much attention in philosophical
issues. Especially in the grammatical works we find explicit philosophical
reflections. For instance, Tamil grammatical work of Tolkappiyar, known as Tolkappiyam
and Sanskrit Ashtadhyi of Panini, contain not just literary norms and notions
but have deeper insights on language and reality. Bhartrhari is a celebrated
philosopher of language in the ancient period.
His Treatise on Sentences and words and his development of theory of
sphota are worth mentioning. For him sphota is a linguistic entity distinct
from a word’s sounds. Classical Nyaya philosophers joined the group and
developed a strong philosophy of language in Indian tradition. These Indian
philosophers of language debated mainly on i) the search for minimal meaningful
units, and (ii) the ontological status of composite linguistic units. In the
ancient period with the grammarians search for the meaningful units was given
much attention. In the later period the linguistic reflection was more on the
ontological status of composite linguistic units. (Bronkhorst 1998)
The Meaning of
‘meaning’
‘Artha’ is used to denote ‘meaning.’ Meaning can be
the meaning of words, sentences as well as nonlinguistic gestures and signs.
Various Indian theories of meaning, testify to the differences prevailing among
philosophical schools with regard to their ontological and epistemological
positions, their focus on a certain type of discourse, and the ultimate purpose
in theorizing. Meaning can be primary, secondary, suggested or intended
meaning. When a verbal cognition results from the primary signification
function of a word, the object or content of that cognition is called primary
meaning. When a verbal cognition results from the secondary signification
function of a word, the object or content of that cognition is called secondary
meaning. When a verbal cognition results from the suggestive signification
function of a word, the object or content of that cognition is called suggested
meaning. When a verbal cognition results from the intentional signification
function of a word, the object or content of that cognition is called intended
meaning. With this realistic ontology in mind, Nyaya-Vaisesika argue that if
the relation between a word and its artha were a natural ontological relation,
there should be real experiences of burning and cutting in one’s mouth after
hearing words like agni (‘fire’) and asi (‘sword’). Therefore the relationship
between a word and the object must be a conventional one (samketa), the
convention being established by God as part of his initial acts of creation. It
is through this established conventional relationship that a word reminds the
listener of its meaning.
Mimamsa school developed a full-scale theory of
ontology and an important theory of meaning. The Vedic scriptural texts are
eternal and uncreated and they are meaningful. In this system the relationship
between a word and its meaning is innate and eternal. For various schools of
Buddhism, language relates only to a level of conceptual constructions, which
have no direct relationship to the actual state of the world. Theravada and the
Vaibhasikas argued that a word refers to a thing which, in reality, is nothing
but a composite entity made up of components which are momentary and in a
continual flux. The components, the momentary atomic elements (dharma), are
presumed to be more real, but words do not refer to this level of reality. Thus
language gives us a less than true picture of what is out there. Other schools
of Buddhism, such as Vijnavada, reduced everything to fleeting states of
consciousness (vijnjna). From this point of view, the objects referred to by
words are more like fictions (vikalpa) or illusions (maya). (Deshpande 1998)
Meaningfulness and Ontological Status of Linguistic
Units
From the Vedic tradition of giving etymological
explanation to names and terms related to their sacrificial practice and
utterances, mantras, Vedic search for meaning of linguistic unit had begun. In
Yaska’s Nirukta, etymological treatise, only nouns and adjectives are said to
be etymologically explained where as verbal forms could not be. Panini’s
grammar furnishes stems and affixes on the basis of a semantic input, and these
stems and affixes are subsequently joined together, and modified where
necessary, so as to yield words and sentences . For Panini these ultimate
meaningful constituents are really meaningful than the ‘surface forms.’
Panini’s sutra 1.2.45, recognizes three meaningful entities, namely verbal
roots, nominal stems and suffixes. He indicates that words and sentences are
considered to have a composite meaning. (Bronkhorst 1998)
The ontological status of linguistic units is answer
the questions like whether words and sentences really exist. If so, how can
they, given that the phonemes that constitute them do not occur simultaneously?
Since, moreover, simultaneous occurrence is a condition for the existence of
collective entities, do individual phonemes exist? They, too, have a certain duration,
and consist therefore of parts that do not occur simultaneously. For the
Sarvastivadins of Buddhism dharmas, constitute all that is. There are three
dharmas, namely, phonemes (vyanjanakayas), words (namakaya) and sentences
(padakaya). These are exiting entities but momentary. For Patanjali too
phonemes and words are eternal. In Bhartrhari this notion played a vital role
as he held that more comprehensive totalities are more real than their
constituent parts. During the period of
Patanjali and Bhartrhari the discussion was centered on the linguistic unit as
meaning-bearer. The meaningless individual phonemes came to be separated from
that of meaningful words, grammatical elements (stems and affixes) and
sentences. In Bhartrhari’s philosophy of language linguistic units and the
‘objects’ they refer to are treated parallel.
(Bronkhorst 1998)
Sphota Theory
Patanjali and Bhartrhari use the word sphota to
refer to linguistic entities conceived of as different from the sounds that
reveal them. For Patanjali, the sphota does not necessarily convey meaning; he
uses the term also in connection with individual phonemes. For Bhartrhari, the
sphota is a meaning-bearer, different from the sounds that manifest it. For him
sphota might be a mental entity or the universal residing in the manifesting
sounds. Sphota as meaning-bearing or not, became point of contention and
discussion rather than the question what exactly sphota is. The question of
meaningfulness of a sequence of phonemes each without meaning, had been
answered variously. According to some, a sequence of sounds can express
meaning; they have to show how it does so. Others hold that this is not
possible; they solve the problem by postulating the existence of the sphota. In
his Slokavarttika Kumarila Bhatta of Mimamsa tradition gives the classical
expositions of both these positions. Bhatta accepts the eternal existence of
individual phonemes. Though the constituent phonemes of a word are not
pronounced simultaneously, they are remembered together the moment the last
phoneme is uttered. Mandana Misra in his Sphotasiddhi protests against the idea
of the combined memory of the phonemes that constitute a word. The sphota is
directly perceived: it is gradually revealed by the phonemes. In the sixteenth
century, Nagesa Bhatta through his various treatises dealt on sphota doctrine.
The Sphotavada enumerates eight types of sphota: (1) phoneme, (2) word, (3)
sentence, (4) indivisible word, (5) indivisible sentence, (6)
phoneme-universal, (7) word-universal, (8) sentence-universal. These sphotas
are primarily meaning-bearers. Nagesa affirms the idea that only sentences
really exist, that words and grammatical elements are no more than imaginary.
The sentence-sphota is most important. During Nagesa’s period again, the
conflict existed between the two major issues of grammar namely, the search for
minimal meaningful units on the one hand, and the ontological status of
composite linguistic units on the other. For Nagesa, finally, only the sentence
is ‘real’, rather than words and smaller grammatical elements. Grammar is
concerned with the smallest identifiable meaningful elements and the way they
combine to form larger units. (Bronkhorst 1998)
Sentence-meaning
Most schools of Indian philosophy have an atomistic
view of meaning and the meaning-bearing linguistic unit. A sentence is put
together by combining words and words are put together by combining morphemic
elements such as stems, roots and affixes. The word-meaning may be viewed as a
fusion of the meanings of stems, roots and affixes, and the meaning of a
sentence may be viewed as a fusion of the meanings of its constituent words.
Beyond this generality, different schools have specific proposals. Prabhakara
proposes that the words of a sentence already convey contextualized/connected
meanings (anvitabhidhana) and that the sentence-meaning is not different from a
simple addition of these inherently connected word-meanings. The Naiyayikas and
the Bhatta propose that the words of a sentence taken by themselves convey uncontextualized/unconnected
meanings, and that these uncontextualized word-meanings are subsequently
brought into a contextualized association with each other (abhihitanvaya).
Therefore, sentence-meaning is different from word-meanings, and is communicated
through the concatenation (samsarga) of words rather than by the words
themselves. This is also the view of the early grammarians such as Patanjali
and Katyayana. For the later grammarian-philosopher Bhartrhari, however, there
are no divisions in speech acts and in communicated meanings. He says that only
a person ignorant of the real nature of language believes the divisions of
sentences into words, stems, roots and affixes to be real. Such divisions are
useful fictions and have an explanatory value in grammatical theory, but have
no reality in communication. In reality, there is no sequence in the cognitions
of these different components. The sentence-meaning becomes an object or
content of a single flash of cognition (pratibha). (Deshpande 1998)
All schools of Indian Philosophy accept the true
cognition as characterised by ‘self-consistency’ (samvada) and
‘uncontradictability’ (abadhitatva). Of course uncontradictability does not
mean as ‘not being contradicted by another true cognition,’ but being in coherence
with other known truths. Logical Positivist theory of the West reduces ‘truth’
only to coherence of a proposition with a set of other propositions previously
accepted as true is not found in Indian traditions. In upholding the theory of
truth there are two major trends among Indian systems. That the Truth is either
‘self-validitating’ (svatah-Pramanyavada), or to be validated by something
other than itself (paratah-Pramanyvada). Samkhya, Mimamsa and Vedanta uphold
the truth to be svatah-pramanya. Nyaya-Vaisesika speak of paratah-pramanyatva
of Truth.
2.10 LET US SUM UP
In Indian philosophy of Language, grammarians were
interested in language and cognition. Nyaya-Vaisesikas were primarily
interested in logic, epistemology and ontology. They argued that a valid
sentence was a true picture of a state of reality. For Mimamsa, meaning had to
be eternal, uncreated and unrelated to a person’s intention. The Buddhists
aimed at showing the emptiness of everything, including language and they
demonstrated how language fails to portray reality.
2.11 KEY WORDS
Picture Theory :
Early Wittgenstein’s theory that language pictures reality.
Sphota Theory :
Indian theory of meaning that refers to linguistic entities conceived of as
different from the sounds that reveal them. Sphota is primarily
meaning-bearers.
UNIT 3 HERMENEUTICAL METHOD: INDIAN AND WESTERN
Contents
3.0 Objectives
3.1 Introduction
3.2 Sabda
3.3 The
Power (Sakti) to Convey Meaning
3.4 Three
Meanings
3.5 Pre-understanding
3.6 The
Semantic Autonomy of the Text
3.7 Towards
a Fusion of Horizons
3.8 The
Hermeneutical Circle
3.9 The
True Scandal of the Text
3.10 Literary
Forms
3.11 Let Us
Sum up
3.12 Key
Words
3.13 Further
Readings and References
3.0 OBJECTIVES
While dealing with the question of understanding, we
must be able to formulate key guiding principles of hermeneutics. To the
extent, through a meaningful dialogue with a text, we understand what
understanding a text means, we can articulate more viable hermeneutical
principles. That is what we envisage in this unit. However, in the first part,
we shall examine hermeneutics from the perspective of Indian Philosophy and we
shall limit this to the study of language in Indian Philosophy.
3.1 INTRODUCTION
Language plays an important role both in the Indian
and the Western hermeneutics. In the West we know of Frege, Russell,
Wittgenstein who are bent upon extolling the role of language in philosophy.
They had influenced the logical positivists of the Vienna circle so much that
the logical positivists were keen on constructing a symbolic language free of
confusion and dubiousness. Let us now turn our attention to some of the
discussions of language in Indian philosophy more specifically in Indian
hermeneutics. To dwell at depth into Indian philosophy of language or Indian
hermeneutics is beyond our scope. We shall therefore restrict ourselves to the
discussions concerning language that emerges from one of the valid means of
knowledge (pramana) in Indian epistemology called sabda. In this unit we
attempt to systematize some of the hermeneutical principles that are at work in
the process of understanding.
3.2 SABDA
Sabda is one of the pramanas in the Indian
epistemology accepted almost by all the important philosophical schools of
India. Sabda is the means to obtain sabda. Sabda is the pramana and sabda is
the resulting knowledge of testimony. Sabda is a sentence spoken by an
authority. An authority is a person who knows the truth and tells the truth
(not all truth but truth pertaining to the point). A sentence is a group of
words. Word is that which has the power (sakti) to convey a meaning. There is
confusion because sabda literally means word. So this understanding of word
includes sentences. There is a lot of controversy between Mimamsakas ans
Nayayikas with regard to the definition of a sentence as group of words. The
discussion hinges on the question, how do you know the meaning of sentence?
According to Mimamsakas, we understand the meaning of a sentence when the words
in the sentence are connected with the verb. But according to Nayayikas, we
understand the meaning of a sentence when the words are connected without
necessarily being connected with the verb.
The Mimamsakas hold that the verb in a sentence is
the most important word and without verb we cannot understand the meaning of a
sentence. For example Devadatta book is a group of word but we do not
understand its meaning unless it is connected with a verb, say for example,
brings. Thus Devadatta brings book conveys the meaning. Similarly, Devadatta
home has no meaning but Devadatta goes home conveys the meaning of a sentence.
Verbs deal with action and according to Mimasakas, the action is the most
important thing. The action of going is qualifies, specified or limited to this
particular person goes. It is the action of going, which has Devadatta s it
subject and home for it s object. The reason why Mimamsakas emphasize verbs is
because according to them salvation is attained by ritual works. They are ritual
activists. Upanisads react against this and say that one must renounce
everything and become a sanyasin, In Upanisads, there are also certain passages
pertinent to the ritual works. For Mimamsakas these passages are primary and
the passages dealing with Brahman are secondary. For Advaita Vedantins what is
said about Brahman is primary ritual injunctions are secondary. But according
to Nyaya-Vaisesikas, we need only connection between as words in a sentence and
verb is not necessary. They give the example, Kancyam Tribhuvanatilah bhupatih.
Kanchyam means in Kanch, bhupatih means protector of earth, therefore it refers
to the king. Tribhuvanatilah is the name of the king though his name means
climax of three worlds. So the translation is, in Kanchi, King Tribhuvanatilah.
There is no verb in this sentence, yet meaning is conveyed.
3.3
THE POWER (SAKTI) TO CONVEY MEANING
A word has the power to convey the meaning. Is this
power God-made or human convention (for example people agree kamala means
lotus). There is a controversy between Nyaya-Vaisesikas on this point. Ancient
Nyaya-Vaisesikas say that the meaning is fixed by God, God fixes especially the
names like kamala etc. and personal names are conventions. Some say that God
fixes even personal names. Modern Nyaya-Vaisesikas say meaning of all words is
a matter of convention. Mimamsakas say that the power (sakti) to convey meaning
is a separate category (padartha) like dravya (substance). They come to the
conclusion by elimination. But Nayayikas would not accept It as a separate
padartha because of some problems. For example, the word pankaja means lotus.
We Panka means mud and ja means born, so pankaja means that which is born in
mud. Not only lotus, but there are other things in mud. If sakti is a separate
padratha we will have to admit different meanings to pankaja.
There are four theories: Kevalavyaki, Kevalajati,
Jati Visita-Vyakti and Apoha. Kevalvyakti only the individual (Kevala means
only, vyakti means individual) For example, father tells the son ghatamanya
(bring the jar). What does the word jar conveys – this particular jar, jarness
or jar and jarness? Jar is Vkyati: jarness is jati. According to this theory,
only the individual jar is meant not the jarness. This is a view hold by modern
Nayayikas. They say that suppose jar means jati, then ghatamanya means bring
the jarness. But you cannot bring the jarness, you can bring only the
individual jar. Those who say ghata actually refers to jati, therefore jarness
object to this saying, then we will have to have different words for different
jars because jarness is not involved. It is not practical, so it refers to
jati.
Kevalajati is proposed by Mimamsakas. The word ghata
conveys the meaning of jati (class). Jati also include vyakti (individual jar),
but the reference to individual jar is only by implication and therefore
secondary. Jati visista-Vyakti is proposed by ancient Nayayikas. The word ghata
refers to vyakti which is qualified by a jati. So, both are involved. Thus when
the word ghata is used it fulfils three functions – it points to a particular
jar, it also signifies that this particular jar is similar to all other jars in
the world and it also distinguishes jars from non-jars like trees, stones, etc.
Apoha –exclusion is held by one type of Buddhists who are idealists and believe
that we cannot know the external reality. When a person says ghata, neither is
there are jar actually, no it refers to a jati. It is a mere idea, only a
concept. What is ghata then? It is a word in reference to something which is
not actually existing, which separates it from other things. A ghata is not a
pata. Their point is we cannot know a thing in itself. That’s why it is called
apoha.
3.4 THREE MEANINGS
Every world is capable of conveying three meanings –
abhida, laksana, vynjana. Abidha means primary or direct meaning. Laksana means
secondary or implied meaning. Vynjana means suggestion. Vynjana is not accepted
by Nyaya-Vaisesikas. Let us explain it with an example – gangayam ghosah. Its
primary meaning is village on the Ganges. This primary meaning is not
acceptable because village cannot be on the on the Ganges. This primary meaning
is not acceptable, we move to laksana or the secondary meaning. Its secondary
meaning is village on the bank of the Ganges. Those who accept Vynjana would
say that the person referring to the village on the bank of the Ganges suggests
the idea of coolness. This is found in poetry. But Nyaya-Vaisesikas do not
accept this.
The power (sakti) to convey the meaning of a word
takes place in three ways – Yoga, rudhi and yogarudha. Yoga means etymology.
Through etymology we come to know the meaning of a word. Such a word is called
yaugika word. For example, pacaja is derived from paca, which means cooking.
Therefore pacaja means a cook. Here the word pacaja conveys its meaning through
etymology. Rudhi means customary meaning. It is not the etymology that conveys
the meaning of a word but people have conferred on it a conventional meaning.
The word may or may not have an etymology but it is not significant. Yogarudha
is combination of etymology and customary meaning. For example, the
etymological meaning of Pankaja is that which is born in mud but by convention
it is confined only to lotus that is born in mud. Similarly the etymological
meaning of madhukara is one who makes honey and by convention it is confined to
bee. The same can be said of hastin whose etymological meaning is one who
possesses hand and by convention it is referred to elephant.
Laksana means implication and they are of three
kinds – jahallaksana, ajahallaksana and jahalajahallaksana. Jahat means
abandoning so in jahallaksana the primary meaning (abidha) is totally
abandoned. For example, the primary meaing of mancah krosanti is beds are
crying. But beds do not cry, so the implied meaning is children on bed are
crying. Therefore, the meaning of bed is totally abandoned. In ajahallaksana
the primary meaning is not abandoned but in addition, there is an implied
meaning. For example, the primary meaning of chatunah yanti is umbrellas are
going. What is implied here is human persons carrying umbrellas are going. The
primary meaning however is retained because the umbrellas move along with the
persons carrying them. In the case of jahalajahallaksana, the primary meaning
is partly kept and partly abandoned. For example when someone says, This is
Devadatta, the meaning of Devadatta si retained while the qualifications of
Devadatta of yesterday etc. are abandoned.
3.5 PRE-UNDERSTANDING
Understanding presupposes pre-understanding. Understanding
is a process and is built upon pre-understanding. Human person is ever becoming
and is in the process of growth. Understanding is part of this process. Thus
pre-understanding consists not merely of the acts of understanding but to the
whole growth process that is at work in every act of understanding.
Understanding something therefore implies understanding it from the viewpoint
of certain questions raised by ones pre-understanding. Let us take the simple
example of the tree. There are different people who are concerned about it: the
botanist, the ecologist, the woodcutter, the carpenter, the tribal etc. Each
one of them understands it differently because each one of them raises
questions from different perspective. Thus for the botanist the issue is, what
family or species does the tree belong to? for the ecologist, will the tree be
cut down by the developmental officers? for the woodcutter, how much money can
I gain by chopping this tree? for the carpenter, what kind of furniture can I
make out of this? and for the tribal, how can I prevent anyone from uprooting
this tree that is the abode of the spirits of my ancestors? Thus the tree will
be understood differently - according to each of these questions. Each of them
is posed by a different kind of pre-understanding.
In the process of understanding, the thing to be
understood strikes the one who understands according to his or her
pre-understanding. It is pre-understanding that determines the kind of
questions the person who wants to understand raises. Thus no understanding is
possible without pre-understanding and the questions it raises. Bultmann
expresses this in his The Problem of Hermeneutics in the collection of Glauben
und Verstehen: Every understanding like every interpretation is continually
oriented by the way the question is put and by standpoint. This it is never
without a pre-understanding of the matter it is questioning the text about.
Understanding means precisely responding to the issue that the
pre-understanding raises. This explains why we have interest in something and
noninterest in other things. Both interest and non-interest are testimonies to
pre-understanding itself.
If we wish to understand what is at work in every
act of understanding, we must pay attention to our pre-understanding or
prejudgments (not yet the final judgment but the stage antecedent to it, in the
court of law it refers to the stage where the advocates sum up their
arguments). This is because our pre-understanding determines both the choice as
well as the direction of our search for meaning. The pre-understanding of
Nietzsche shapes his understanding God as the supreme power who makes merry at
the fragility of the humans and thus restoring human dignity consists in
killing him. Our search for meaning and truth is shaped by and large by our
prejudgments. This should help us to be aware that we look at reality from a
particular perspective and what is meaningful from one perspective may be
absurd from another. We can cite a number of examples from within religious
traditions. God as Trinity that is profound and insightful within the Christian
tradition is prone to be pointless within the Jewish or Islamic tradition of
monolithic monotheism. The point is well made - the point of departure for
understanding is pre-understanding. This will help us not to absolutize our way
of looking at reality.
3.6 THE SEMANTIC AUTONOMY OF THE TEXT
If pre-understanding shapes our understanding, the
presumption of objectivity (the concern of epistemology is at stake. There is
no such thing as an objective reading of a text. To get to know the mind of the
author whether dead or living is naive and inessential. Hence the text as it
has come of age must speak for itself. Suppose if the author makes further
comments on what he originally intended in his literary work (art, poem, play,
film etc.) what status does it occupy? Once the text leaves the desk of the
author it is autonomous and his extra-textual comments must be on par with the
views of others. On the other hand, we should not fall into the trap of what
Ricoeur calls the fallacy of the absolute text. A text is not an authorless
entity - it remains a discourse said by someone to someone else about
something. It is impossible to cancel out this main characteristic of discourse
without reducing texts to natural objects, ie, to things which are not man-made
but which, like pebbles, are found in the sand. For Ricoeur, there are two
extremes and both are to be avoided. One extreme is the dependence of the text
on the intention of the author because primarily we can never know the mind of
the author and secondly any rich text will have more than one meaning. Another
extreme is doing what one wants with the text as if the text has no author at
all.
Ricoeur in this context speaks of the semantic axis
of the text. There are certain limits within which a text needs to be
interpreted. There are two aspects at work in the process of understanding -
the semiotic stage and the semantic stage. The semiotic stage is the decoding
of the complex set of codes and the semantic stage is where the meaning
emerges. (These are not really two stages because meaning emerges in the act of
decoding.) It is here that the reader has to apply the hermeneutic of suspicion
- whether he or she reads meaning into the text. For this purpose he or she has
to rely on the text as a whole and discover the axis around which the whole
text revolves. One can employ any method to study the text as a whole. The
semantic axis shows how the text hangs together and what holds it together. But
even if an interpretation goes against the original intention of the author it
is equally a valid interpretation, provided it is well within the overall
thrust of the text. This is to say that we cannot distort the meaning of the
text by selective reading, omitting some elements and exaggerating other
elements according to our convenience and vested interest. The semantic
autonomy of the text is not a pretext to make the text say what one wants
according to ones whims and fancies.
3.7 TOWARDS A FUSION OF HORIZONS
We are indebted
to Gadamar for the original and significant contribution of his
fusion of horizons. The text has its own horizon of its own and the reader has
his or her own horizon. The horizon of the text includes the context and the
life situation of the author in which the text emerged and also the successive
readings it has gone through. The more a text is historically distant the
broader its horizon. The horizon of the present reader refers to the readers
life situation inclusive of his or her pre-understanding. The semantic autonomy
of the text paves way for the fusion between the horizon of the text and of the
reader. The reader approaches the text with his own pre-understanding to understand
the text and its meaningfulness for him or her for his life in the present
situation. Thus the preoccupations of hermeneutics have come to a full circle:
from the concern of what lies behind the text (the authors intention) to what
lies in the text (what the text says) towards what lies in front of the text
(the emergence of meaning with the fusion of the horizon of the text with that
of the reader).
3.8 THE HERMENEUTICAL CIRCLE
Suppose we are given a book written in a totally
foreign language (say Hebrew or Greek) we can only stare at it. No
understanding is possible because we have no point of entry into the world of
the text. On the other hand if it is a simple and plain sentence like The
Hermeneutics class is interesting, there is nothing to interpret because the
meaning is self-evident in this case. Thus the meaning of a text must somehow
be clear but not totally for interpretation to become necessary. Thus says
Dilthey in his Patterns and Meaning in History: Interpretations would be
impossible if expressions of life were completely strange. It would be
unnecessary if nothing was strange in them. It lies, therefore, between two
extremes. Thanks to the hermeneutical circle we can read a text and widen our
understanding or correct our previous understanding of the same.
Understanding, therefore, is basically a referential
operation; we understand something by means of something we already know. A
whole sentence, for instance, is a unity. We understand the meaning of an
individual word by seeing it in reference to the whole of the sentence; and
reciprocally, the meaning of the sentence as a whole is dependent on the
meaning of individual words. By dialectical interaction between the whole and
the part, each gives the other meaning; understanding is circular then. Because
within this circle the meaning comes to stand, we call this the hermeneutical
circle.
The circularity of understanding implies that there
is no true starting point for understanding because every part presupposes the
others. It seems to suggest a logical contradiction. If we need to understand
the whole before understanding the parts we would have understood nothing. On
the other hand the part can be understood only in reference to the whole. This
brings us to the awareness that there is no such thing as having understood
once and for all. The analogy of the game given by Gadamar is of great
significance here. Understanding can be compared to a game. The game may be
played many times but there is no such thing as the final and the definite
game. Every time the game is played according to the rules of the game, yet
every time played differently, so also is understanding. Every time we play the
game of chess, we understand it better, but we will never arrive at a stage
where we have understood it completely. We begin with the understanding of the
part and grasp the meaning of the whole in the light of our understanding of
the part. In the process, the meaning of the part becomes better understood in
the light of the whole. So there is back and forth in our understanding and
every time we read• the same text we discover the emergence of new meanings.
3.9 THE TRUE SCANDAL OF THE TEXT
In the process of understanding in which the fusion
takes place, not only the text acquires new meanings but the reader is also
challenged by the text. Any text especially the religious text worthy of name
must scandalize us. The English word scandal is derived from the Greek
skandalos meaning a stumbling block. Thus when we speak of a text scandalizing
us we mean the text challenging some of our ideas and actions that are
dehumanizing. Ricoeur points out that every hermeneutics is, explicitly or
implicitly, self-understanding by means of understanding others. In this
context, we can make a distinction between true scandal and false scandal. The
true scandal of the text is the meaning emerging from the text having the
ability to clarify our pre-understanding and in the process to critically
challenge them. What we uphold to be true and correct conventionally may be
called into question. We should remember the role of the tradition that
influences the way we see reality. We live by certain myths provided by our
tradition. These myths are so powerful that they can grip us to the extent that
we do not realize them as myths and are to be demythologized. It is Bultmann
who introduces this concept of demythologization. He is critiqued on the ground
that we cannot live without myths, hence what we need to do is not
demythologization but remythologization. But what Bultmann meant by
demythologization is not doing away with myths but to identify and recognize
them as myths. This will enable us and our presumptions to be challenged by
encountering a text, say like the Bible.
In order to understand the false scandal of the text,
it is better to make a distinction between what is said and how it is said.
What is said is the meaning of the text. How something is said refers to the
vehicle by which the message is transported. This vehicle is inclusive of the
knowledge of the tradition in which the text came to be. This knowledge is
inclusive of cosmology, anthropology, theology and so on. But it is not this
knowledge that is communicated but through which something else is
communicated. Hence as Ricoeur says, we must make attempts to overcome the
distance between the cultural epoch to which the text belongs and the
interpreter himself. Thus, on dealing with any text we must take pains in
separating the meaning and the cultural vehicle through which the meaning is
passed on.
It is in this connection that Bultmanns
demythologization becomes important. As we have made reference earlier, his
demythologization is more often misunderstood than understood. He does not
intend to purge away the mythical elements and reduce the text to shallow
literalism. Far from it, he wants to emphasize the original meaning embodied in
myths. These myths do not provide us cosmological information but challenge us
as powerful symbols summoning us to a radical and new self-understanding.
3.10 LITERARY FORMS
When we glance through a newspaper, we see a variety
of literary forms. There is an editorial - a critical analysis of some
significant events. Its purpose is not merely to state facts but also to
evaluate them form a specific point of view. We find reporting of events, which
is aimed to give a factual account of what had happened. It is true that no two
newspapers report the same event in the same way. There may be disagreements on
what is known as facts but they may not be diametrically opposed to the happening
of an event. Thus for instance, the figure of death toll in an earthquake may
vary according to different news reports but no paper would refuse that the
earthquake took place. There is a special section on comics in every newspaper,
of course, meant to make us burst into laughter. All newspapers are flooded
with advertisements with an end to sell goods and commodities. Obviously to
achieve this end, exaggerated statements are made in advertisements. We are
familiar with famous phrases such as the complete man, better than the best,
made for each other and so on. We do not take these statements or catchy
slogans in the advertisements as gospel truths. When we read the newspaper, we
quickly recognize these different literary forms and interpret them
accordingly.
From our ordinary experience of reading newspapers,
we shall now try to make a workable definition of literary forms. A literary
form is a manner or a style by which particular information is passed on to
achieve a specific end and is judged by the effective means it applies to
realize the end. It becomes clear that the criteria of judging one literary
form cannot be applied to another. A good joke is one that makes us laugh and a
good advertisement is one that persuades us to buy the commodity it advertises.
These are two different literary forms. We don’t reject an advertisement
because it does not make us laugh or we don’t reject a joke because it contains
no factual description of an event. It would be a grave mistake if we were to
do so. Hence it is important to identify the literary form of a text before we
begin to interpret it. Obviously we cannot interpret Shakespeares Macbeth in
the way we would interpret Karl Marx Das Capital.
Wittgenstein uses the analogy of language games.
Each game has got its own rules. Applying the rules of football to cricket or
basketball to judge football would be foolish. Likewise every discipline is a
literary form in its own right and the rules of one are not applicable for
another. Thus for instance when a poet describes the beauty of a gin by
comparing it with the full moon it has to be acknowledged as poetic. We should
not apply the rules of astronomy that the gin is a celestial thing. This is all
the more important in the religious language that is symbolic and has to be
acknowledged as such.
3.11
LET US SUM UP
We have discussed in the beginning the significance
of Indian hermeneutics particularly that of sabda. We have also seen how
language plays an important role in hermeneutics both from the Indian and the
Western philosophical points of view. Some of the key hermeneutical principles
are also discussed at length to enable the students to apply these principles
in their textual reading and to make an authentic interpretation of the text
and deepen their understanding.
3. 12 KEY WORDS
pramana: Means of knowledge.
Sabda: Verbal testimony.
laksana: Implication.
Semantic Axis: The axis which shows how the text
hangs together and what holds it together.
The Semantic Autonomy of the Text: Once the text
leaves the desk of the author it is autonomous and his extra-textual comments
must be on par with the views of others.
Scandal: The English word scandal is derived from
the Greek skandalos meaning a stumbling block.
Demythologization: identifying and recognizing myths
as myths
UNIT 4 DECONSTRUCTIVE METHOD
Contents
4.0 Objectives
4.1 Introduction
4.2 The
Seminal Idea of Deconstruction in Heidegger
4.3 Deconstruction
in Derrida
4.4 Structuralism
and Post-structuralism
4.5 Sign,
Signifier and Signified
4.6 Writing
and Trace
4.7 Deconstruction
as a Strategic Reading
4.8 The
Logic of Supplement
4.9 No
Outside-text
4.10 Difference
4.11 Let Us
Sum up
4.12 Key
Words
4.13 Further
Readings and References
4.0 OBJECTIVES
It is very hard to restrict deconstruction as a
method. In fact, the key thinker of deconstruction, Jacques Derrida has always
resisted pinning it down as a method. However, in this unit, we shall briefly
discuss the various aspects of deconstruction starting from its seminal idea
found in Heidegger. In order to have a better grasp of deconstruction as a
strategy, we also deal with related concepts in Derrida’s Philosophy such as
difference, trace, supplement and arche-writing.
4.1
INTRODUCTION
Deconstruction is
a method or a school of philosophy today. This practice of
textual analysis is used to dissect numerous writings (philosophy and
literature), to reveal their shifts and confusions of meaning by means of a
reading focusing on the assumptions implied and omissions unveiled by the text
itself. This concept, participating in both philosophy and literature, won a
great reputation in the United States of America, where it is equated with the
postmodern philosophy, and more generally to the different approach of
continental philosophy in Europe. If the term “deconstruction” was first used
by Heidegger, it is the work of Derrida which has systematized its use and
theorized its practice.
4.2 THE SEMINAL IDEA OF DECONSTRUCTION IN
HEIDEGGER
The term deconstruction in Derrida appears for the
first time in Of Grammatology translated without explicit Heideggerian terms.
Derrida explained that he wished “among other things,” to provide a translation
for the German terms of Destruktion and Abbau, that Heidegger employs in Being
and Time, Derrida believes that his translation is more relevant than the
classical translation of Destruktion and Abbau as destruction, insofar as it
does not refer so much to the destruction of metaphysics, to reduce it to
nothingness, than to show how it was built.
Both Destruktion and Abbau in this context meant an
operation on the structure or traditional architecture of the founding concepts
of ontology or of Western metaphysics. But in French the term “destruction” too
obviously implied annihilation, a negative reduction closer to the “demolition”
found in Nietzsche, which Derrida rejected. In fact, the word deconstruction
appeared from 1955 in French philosophy in the context of the translation of
the text of Heidegger “Contributions to the question of Being” (Zur
Seinsfrage). Granel Gerard chose this term “deconstruction” to translate Abbau
the German word that he wanted to distinguish from “destruction” (translation
of Zerstörung). In Heidegger’s Being and Time (Sein und Zeit), Destruktion
addresses the concept of time, it must be shown by successive steps the
experience of time was covered by metaphysics, making us forget the original
meaning of being as a temporal being. The three steps of this deconstruction
will go down the history of Western Philosophy:
1. Kant’s
doctrine of schematic and time as the preliminary step of a problematic of
temporality.
2. The
ontological foundation of the cogito ergo sum of Descartes and the resumption
of the medieval ontology in the problematic of res cogitans.
3. The
treatise of Aristotle on time as discrimen of the phenomenal base and limits of
the ancient ontology.
However, if Heidegger announces this deconstruction
at the end of the Introduction to Sein und Zeit, this part of the book, which
was to be, according to the plan of 1927, was never written as such. At most,
we can consider his other works and conferences that partially touch upon it,
starting with the book Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, published in 1929.
4.3 DECONSTRUCTION IN DERRIDA
In reflecting on
his own and recovering the notion of deconstruction,
Derrida intended the meaning of a given text (essay, novel, newspaper article)
is the result of the difference between the words used, rather than referring
to things they represent; it is an active difference, working in the hollow
sense of each word, in a manner analogous to the differential meaning of
Saussurean linguistics. To mark the active nature of this difference (instead
of the passive nature of the difference relative to judgments about
contingent), Derrida suggests the term differance, a sort of portmanteau word
combining the present participle of the verb “to differ” and “to defer”. In
other words, different meanings of a text can be found by decomposing the
structure of language in which it is written.
Deconstruction is not intended as a method, nor a
philosophical system, but rather a practice. His detractors often accuse him of
its convoluted meaning. On the day of the demise of Derrida, the New York
Times, written by Jonathan Kandell, headlined thus: “abstruse theorist is
dead.” Unloved and paradoxically little known in France, where deconstruction
remains attached to the figure of Derrida, it has been subjected to violent
attacks both in the continental Europe and in the United States of America as
well. Derrida has replied to a particularly aggressive criticism of the
American philosopher John Searle in his book, Limited Inc. (the book’s title is
a pun on the name of the philosopher: “Inc”. is a rough translation of the
French SARL).
4.4 STRUCTURALISM AND POST-STRUCTURALISM
The term
“post-structuralism” refers to a critical perspective
that emerged in the seventies and dethroned structuralism as the dominant
figure of thought of language and text. To understand post-structuralism, it
must be considered in relation to structuralism. Deconstructionist critics
agreed with the poststructuralist view of language, according to which a
signifier (form of a sign) does not refer to a defined signified (the content
of a sign), but only to other signifiers.
Derrida opposes the centre inherent in the
structuralism of the structure. With Claude Levi-Strauss as a representative of
structuralist thought, Derrida shows that with the prohibition of incest, the
nature/culture opposition and the universal/normative structure can no longer
hold: “The incest prohibition is universal [natural], but it is also a
prohibition, a system of norms and prohibitions [culture].” Derrida rejects the
metaphysical history and the hierarchical dichotomies that have survived so far
and on which all logical reasoning (logos, meaning speech) of the world was
founded. Derrida rejects structuralism and the Saussurean schema (the relation
between signifier and signified) is therefore revised. The structure that
Derrida rejects is the binary opposition signifier/signified. This structure is
in fact the structure of the history of thought, which conceives the world in
terms of a system of oppositions leading to infinity: logos/pathos, soul/body,
same/other, good/evil, culture/nature, man/woman, intelligible/sensible, inside/outside,
memory/forgetfulness, speech/writing, day/night, etc.
4.5 SIGN, SIGNIFIER AND SIGNIFIED
In order to properly explain the theory of Derrida,
which falls both on philosophical and semiotic framework, it is important to
define the concepts that shape his thought. Given the close weaving of several
of these concepts with one another and the impossibility of defining one
without considering the other, each of these brings together several concepts.
The relation between the signifier and the signified is no longer one of
structuralism. Hence, there are two ways of erasing the difference between the
signifier and the signified; the classical one consists in submitting sign to
thought, the other precisely is to challenge the system in which the preceding
reduction functioned starting from the opposition between the sensible and the
intelligible. Note that, according to structuralism, the signifier is the
sensible part of the sign, for it is grasped by the senses thus allowing us to
have access to the signified. As far as the signified is concerned, it
corresponds to the idea, to the immaterial and intelligible concept. It is this
opposition that Derrida criticizes. The
Derridean concept of the sign is thus always linked to the structure of the
Western philosophy. The direct relationship between the signifier and the
signified is revisited. Let us take the example of water: While reading the
word “water,” we can think of drops of water, a lake, the chemical symbol H2O,
etc. We do not necessarily think of a still image of water, a universal mental
representation. Thus each concept (meaning) to which the “water” may refer,
sends back to another signifier. This infinite chain of signifier to signifier
results in an endless game and opens the text, shifts it and makes it moving.
4.6 WRITING AND TRACE
Words refer to other words. The grammatology of
Derrida proposes that writing is originary in the same way as voice, a constant
tension without power struggle. Therefore writing cannot be a reproduction of
the spoken language since neither came first; similarly, writing is not a
simple written form of a word, but the articulation and inscription of the
trace. The trace conveys the impossibility of the origin and of a centre. It is
the non-origin of the origin. It is the absolute origin of sense in general. In
the words of Derrida, “the trace is the differance which opens appearance
[l’apparaître] and signification.” He further asserts that if it belongs to the
movement of signification, then “signification is a priori written, whether
inscribed or not, in one form or another, in a ‘sensible’ and ‘spatial’ element
that is called ‘exterior’.” It is also significant to note that Derrida
considers the trace as an arche-writing not only because it is the first
possibility of spoken word but also because it is the first possibility of
written word (graphie).
The concept of “graphie” depends on trace in so far
as the latter is the common possibility to all communication systems. When we
associate the trace with the graph (gestural, visual, pictorial, musical,
verbal), the trace becomes gram (letter). Only at this point appears outside
(opposite of inside), as a spatial and objective exteriority. The arche-writing
of which Derrida speaks is in fact a generalized form of writing to be
understood in terms of differance. This difference (the a here is the trace and
the gram), as temporalization, is itself the trace of the written in the spoken
word. For example, the punctuation marks are supplement to speech, and not its
reproduction.
According to Derrida, the text cannot be explained
by its origin source (author, society, history or context), since repetition is
at the origin. The text is writing and writing is unintentional language. It is
language in relation to speech that implements it. However, only reading makes
the text and writing possible. What characterizes writing is textuality, which
is both closure and non-closure of the text. As Derrida states in his
monumental work Writing and Difference, “One can conceive of the closure of
that which is without end. Closure is the circular limit within which the
repetition of difference infinitely repeats itself. That is to say, closure is
its playing space. This movement is the movement of the world as play.”
4.7 DECONSTRUCTION AS A STRATEGIC READING
The method of deconstruction is not negative.
Deconstruction is primarily to reverse the principles of Western philosophy by
emphasizing the role of margin and non-privileged, with the basic concepts
under erasure in order to demonstrate how these principles were designed and
their opposites, neglected. In an attempt to explain his project, Derrida
remarked that an opposition of metaphysical binary concepts such as
speech/writing and presence/absence is not merely an opposition but it
establishes a hierarchy and an order of subordination. Derrida was interested
in a particular opposition, the opposition between speech and writing.
Deconstruction cannot proceed immediately to neutralization: it must – by a
double gesture, a double science, a double writing – practice an overturning of
the classical opposition in the system. Thus deconstruction takes place in two
stages. First is the phase of reversal, since the binary pair is hierarchical,
we must first destroy the exercise of power by one term of the pair over the
other. Writing must take precedence over speech, the other over the same and
the absence over the presence. Next comes the phase of neutralization. The
binary logic and its dual thinking have to be totally uprooted. Thus the new
terms become undecidable, thus making them unclassifiable and they amalgamate
the two poles previously opposed.
In his essay titled “Plato's Pharmacy,” Derrida has
adopted a deconstructive reading of Plato’s famous work Phaedrus, in which
opposites poles meet and merge. Phaedrus recounts the myth that Theuth, the
inventor of writing proposed to King Thamus writing as a remedy against
forgetfulness, but the king considered writing as a poison as it kills the live
memory. Thus the term pharmakon can mean both cure and poison; the same word
has two opposite contexts. While Teuth uses this word in the sense of cure, the
king chose the meaning of poison. Derrida in his reading of Phaedrus shows that
pharmakon, both as remedy and poison, already enters into the body of speech
with all its ambivalence. This charm, this virtue of fascination, can be
alternately or simultaneously beneficial and harmful. It is significant that
Socrates himself compares writing, the written text, to a pharmakon. “You seem
to have discovered a drug for getting me out,” he says, “A hungry animal can be
driven by dangling a carrot or a bit of greenstuff in front of it; similarly if
you proffer me speeches bound in books I don’t doubt you can cart me all around
Attica, and anywhere else you please” (Phaedrus 230d-e).
But Derrida is more concerned with this practice
within a given language. What is important to him is that even in the original
text Plato himself was bending the term to fit his needs, namely, stressing the
caustic side of the ‘drug” in association with writing (and myth) to belittle
it in the face of speech. Derrida further adds that “if the pharmakon is
ambivalent, it is because it constitutes the medium in which opposites are
opposed, the movement and the play that links them among themselves, reverses
them or makes one side cross over into the other (soul/body, good/evil,
inside/outside, memory/forgetfulness, speech/writing, etc.).” We can say that
deconstruction shakes the distinctions provided by the ontology, between presence
and absence, between the fullness of life and death; it focuses its attention
on to leaving traces or inheritance beyond the living present of life. Derrida
himself summarizes the operation of deconstruction as a rejection of the
possibility of aggregation. “If totalization no longer has any meaning, it is
not because the infinity of a field cannot be covered by a finite glance or a
finite discourse, but because the nature of the field-that is, language and a
finite language-excludes totalization.” It is finite language which excludes
totalization as language is made up of infinite signifier and signified
functioning inter-changeably and arbitrarily, thereby opening up possibilities
for infinite play and substitution. Derrida explains this free play through the
concept of supplementarity.
4.8 THE LOGIC OF SUPPLEMENT
Derrida deconstructs the hierarchy between speech
and writing through the “logic of supplement.” The term “supplement” is
borrowed from Rousseau, who describes writing as a supplement of speech, the
latter representing the former. The natural condition of language is the speech
and writing presents itself as a dangerous supplement insofar as it does
violence to the natural character of language. The term “supplement” has two
meanings. It can first mean an addition to something which is already
sufficient in itself. But it can also mean something more to accomplish a thing
incapable of self-accomplishment. If writing is a supplement to speech in the
second sense, it can become dangerous. It can affect the naturalness of speech
and can even supplant it.
Admittedly, Rousseau, according to Derrida, repeats
the inaugural movement of Phaedrus. If the history of metaphysics is the
history of the determination of being as presence, if it is intertwined with
that of logocentrism and if it is understood entirely as a reduction of the
trace, the Rousseau’s work seems to occupy a singular situation between the
Phaedrus of Plato and the Encyclopedia of Hegel. Thought is analyzed by speech
while speech is analyzed through writing. The art of writing is only a mediated
representation of thought and representation is the loss of presence.
For Derrida, writing can be a supplement to speech
insofar as the latter can be “supplemented,” that is to say it suffers from a
lack which can be completed. Derrida explains this lack as follows: speech is
not a thought fully present to the listener, but an acoustic symbol
representing thought. Like in the case of writing, speech is only a mediation
of thought and this is why writing can complement it. The alleged derivation of
writing has been possible on one condition: that the language called “original”
has ever existed, it was never touched by the writing, it was always and
already writing.
Writing is indeed a “dangerous supplement,” not
because it could affect the purity of speech, as Rousseau feared, but because
its ability to complement speech and even supplant it shows that speech has
flaws that are usually attributed to writing. Writing is a supplement to the extent
that it fills a lack in speech. This is a new meaning of “dangerous
supplement.” Speech itself is mediation of something and like writing, it is
also a supplement. Note the important thesis of Derrida: a signifier both
completes what it signifies, and adds something new to it. If speech is a
supplement, what it complements must be insufficient in itself, otherwise
speech cannot represent it. What is represented by speech must also be a
supplement and it must signify or represent something else. The result is a
chain of supplements leading to a full and self-sufficient presence. The
consequence of this thesis is that in the language, there is only a chain of
signifiers, each signifier pointing to another signifier.
4.9 NO OUTSIDE-TEXT
The paradox is that a sign can never represent the
presence itself, as presence is self-sufficient, nor can the sign function as a
signifier or supplement. What exists is a world of representations and
representations of representations, ad infinitum. Each signified is also a
signifier for another signified. Derrida describes the final reconstruction of
presence: “there is no outside-text” [“il n’y a pas de hors-texte”]. To better
understand this famous aphorism of Derrida, let us recall that, according to
him, deconstructive reading is installed in the space between what the author
means and what the text says of which the author himself is “taken-up” by
surprise. The deconstructive reading must identify the chasm between what is
said and intended meaning; this is not possible by so-called conventional and
reproductive reading, which is however important, according to Derrida, to
avoid any kind of interpretation: “[Without] all the instruments of traditional
criticism…, critical production would risk developing in any direction and
authorize itself to say almost anything.” And immediately, Derrida recognizes
the inadequacy of this traditional reading despite its importance: “but this
indispensable guard-rail has always only protected, never opened, a reading.”
In all Metaphysics, especially in that of Husserl
and Heidegger, we may find what “exceeds” Metaphysics: the traces of before,
after and outside. But such a reading requires a simultaneous passing through
and transgressing Metaphysics. In this context, Derrida remarks that the only
way to be faithful to a tradition and to keep it alive is to transgress it. In
other words, to keep a tradition alive, we should not be faithful to it to the
point of reproducing it mechanically. We must keep alive the possibility of
reading otherwise, to explore through conventional requirements without
abandoning them, whatever they exclude, marginalize and forget. Deconstructive
reading transgresses this guardrail. This transgression is a passage to limits
and to frontiers, but it evades a transcendental signified which would be
outside text and beyond history; it remains always and already embedded in
social, political and historical networks, which Derrida calls “arche-text” and
sometimes simply “text.”
In this context, the adage “there is no outside
text” means that there is no reference without difference, that is, without the
use of a differential system. “There is no outside-text” does not mean that
there is nothing outside of words, or that everything can be reduced to
linguistic concepts. In the words of Derrida: “I never ceased to be surprised
by critics who see my work as a declaration that there is nothing beyond
language, that we are imprisoned in language; it is, in fact, saying the exact
opposite. The critique of logocentrism is above else the search for the ‘other’
and the other of language.” In his epilogue to Limited Inc., Derrida once again
resumes his definition of text: “I wanted to recall that the concept of text I
propose is limited neither to the graphic, nor to the book, nor even to
discourse, and even less to the semantic, representational, symbolic, ideal, or
ideological sphere. What I call ‘text’ implies all the structures called
‘real,’ ‘economic,’ ‘historical,’ ‘socio-institutional,’ in short: all possible
referents. Another way of recalling once again that ‘there is nothing outside
the text’ ... It does mean that every referent, all reality has the structure
of a differential trace, and that one cannot refer to this ‘real’ except in an
interpretive experience. The latter neither yields meaning nor assumes it
except in a movement of differential referring.”
4.10 DIFFERANCE
The term differance was coined by Derrida when he
gave a lecture in 1968 to the French Society of Philosophy. In itself, it
represents a synthesis of philosophical and semiotic thought of Derrida. All
concepts defined earlier are involved in this theory. The grapheme a points to
several aspects of the practice of this theory:
1. Differance
is the difference that pulls down the cult of identity and dominance of the
same over the other; it means there is no origin or more precisely originary
unity). To differ is not to be identical.
2. Differance
mark a difference in spelling, written by a instead of e; we see this
difference, but we cannot hear it.
3. Differance
evokes the meaning of displacing, eluding and shifting.
4. Differance
is a future in progress (struggle against the fixed meanings); it is the
displacement of signifiers which signify the margins because there is no
original and organized transcendental signified.
The writing of differance refers to itself as it
breaks away from the concepts of signified and referent. The emphasis of the
theme of writing works as an antidote against idealism, metaphysics and
ontology.
4.11 LET US SUM UP
A deconstructionist approach allows us to create a
constant tension between dualisms in any binary opposition, bringing the two
poles of the pair to an equal footing. Thus meanings of words become
undecidable so as to go beyond binary thinking. This theory is adopted by
literary writers, including feminists, who, by the deconstructionist approach
and through the strategy of differance, give rise to new terms that go beyond
the dualisms in general but more specifically beyond the opposition such as
man/woman, self/other and pathos/logos.
To deconstruct, is to go beyond all rigid conceptual
oppositions (masculine/ feminine, nature/culture, subject/object,
sensible/intelligible, past/present, etc.) and not to deal with these concepts
as if they were opposed to each other. Each pole in the binary carries within
it, the trace of the opposite pole. Thus for example, the androgynous person
bears traces both of masculine and feminine, the inclusion of the observer in a
scientific experiment in pursuit of its objective purpose, and the law of
might, which governs the nature reverberate in organizations and social
structures.
4.12
KEY WORDS
Differance: Differance is a play on the French
‘differer,’ which means both “to defer” and “to differ.” Derrida uses both of
these meanings to describe his concept. With words, Derrida suggests, the
meaning is always “deferred” as a single word cannot give a complete
description. A word needs other words to give it context; therefore its meaning
is deferred until more information is given.
Trace: According to Derrida, there is no true
meaning of all human words (and even human thoughts). The meaning of any word
can only be expressed compared to other words. What every word contains within
itself is only shadows of other related words, which Derrida calls trace.
Graphie: written form of a word.
Pharmakon: It meant both the disease and its cure to
the ancient Greeks. It also means both medicine and poison and from which we
get “pharmacy” and “pharmaceutical.”
Logocentrism: It is a term used by Derrida and other
exponents of deconstruction to designate the desire for a centre or original
guarantee of all meanings, which in Derrida’s view has characterized Western
philosophy since Plato. The Greek word logos can just mean “word,” but in
philosophy it often denotes an ultimate principle of truth or reason, while in
Christian theology it refers to the Word of God as the origin and foundation of
all things. Derrida's critique of logocentric thinking shows how it attempts to
repress difference in favour of identity and presence: the philosophical
“metaphysics of presence” craves a “transcendental signified” ultimately
self-sufficient meaning (e.g. God, Man, Truth). The most significant case of
logocentrism is the enduring phonocentrism that privileges speech over writing
because speech is held to guarantee the full ‘presence’ and integrity of
meaning.
Block 4:
Methodology of Preparing Research Paper
UNIT 1 METHOD OF BIBLIOGRAPHY
Contents
1.0 Objectives
1.1. Introduction
1.2 Preparing
to Write
1.3 Writing
a Paper
1.4 The
Main Divisions of a Paper
1.5 Writing
Bibliography in Turabian and APA
1.6 Sample
Bibliography
1.7 Let
us Sum up
1.8 Key
Words
1.9 Further
Readings and References
1.0 OBJECTIVES
• To
study basic human quest for unity that has given rise to philosophy, religion
and science.
• To
trace the origin of human knowledge to our quest for understanding: the self,
world and God.
1.1 INTRODUCTION
In this unit we attempt to offer preliminary remarks
on writing a research paper and on preparing a proper bibliography.
1.2 PREPARING TO WRITE
CHOOSING A TOPIC
Preliminary Remarks
• The
purpose of a research paper is to explore an idea or probe an issue with the
help of available resources in the library.
• Make
a statement of thesis which states clearly the area of your research and
defines the scope of your paper.
• The
findings of the research have to be clearly and coherently presented in an
accepted scientific format.
• A
research paper pays attention both to the content as well as to the style of
presentation.
Content
• Choose
a definite, specific subject.
• The
subject must be of interest to your readers.
• It
should neither be too broad nor too specific
• It
must be within the limits of time and the length of paper.
• It
must have necessary sources available.
• The
sources available should neither be too vast nor too little.
• It
can be author-based or theme-based.
• Make
sure you have a competent guide available to you.
style of presentation
Different disciplines adopt different styles.
We proposes two styles of presentation (Chicago
Style & APA).
You are free to choose one of these but be
consistent.
PREPARING A
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Preliminary Remarks
• Identify
books and articles related to the research. This can be done through browsing
the latest edition of encyclopedias on the subject matter or using search
engine on the internet.
• Make
sure that these books and articles are available to you either in the JDV
Library or in any institutions near-by where you can access them.
• Author-based
research calls for a distinction between primary and secondary sources.
• You
can also include online sources provided they are of academic standard.
Keeping Record of the Sources
• Use
separate card (6” x 4”) for entering then bibliographic information of each
work whether book or article.
• Choose
the most recent edition and the best translation if choices are available in
the library.
• Note
down the complete and precise references of books and articles from the start
in the card including the shelf where they can be located.
• Arrange
the cards in alphabetical order according to the surname of the author. If the
study is author-based, then maintain two sets of cards – one for primary
sources and the other for secondary sources. Arrange the secondary sources in
alphabetical order according to the surname of the author.
• Eventually,
you will transform this into your bibliography.
Necessary Data for a Book
Name of the Library
Call number
Author – Surname followed by given name(s)
Title of the Book in italics
Details of Publication
Personal Remarks
Specimen Bibliography Card for a Book
JDV Library
DO-254-W3
Welsch, David
Nazi Propaganda: The Power and the Limitations
London: Croom Helm, 1983
(This books seems to have 2 particularly useful
chapters)
Necessary Data for an Essay from an Edited Work
Name of the Library
Call Number
Name of the Edited Work in italics
Editor – First name followed by the surname
Author – Surname followed by given name(s)
Title of the Article in double quotes with exact
page numbers
Details of Publication
Personal Remarks
Specimen Card for an Article from a Journal
Name of the Library
Name of the Journal in italics
Author – Surname followed by given name(s)
Title of the Article in double quotes with exact
page numbers
Details of Publication including volume and number
if any
Personal Remarks
PREPARING
NOTES FOR BIBLIOGRAPHY
Preliminary Remarks
• Prepare
a separate dossier for each of the work
• Prepare
a set of cards to note down citations which you think you would quote in your
paper
• You
need to practice the art of omission though you may be tempted to take down
everything
• Equip
yourself with techniques like précis writing and paraphrasing.
• Avoid
reproducing the words of the author instead try to employ your own words.
• Remember
to note down only those citations which you think cannot be said otherwise.
General Tips
• Read
primary sources carefully and secondary sources rapidly, if it is an
author-based research.
• Begin
reading from the book/article recently published on the theme or of the author
if it is an author-based study.
• Look
for striking ideas pertaining to the subject.
• Summarize
the ideas accurately.
• Take
notes accurately by giving reference to the exact page, work, and edition.
• For
passages taken verbatim to be quoted in the text, use standard cards and give
exact reference and organize them thematically.
• For
the summary, use the A4 size paper divided into three unequal parts: the left
side for the summary idea of the author, right side for your comments and
observations, and the bottom for technical words and cross-reference to the
card.
Tips for Personal Critical Comments
• Identifying
arguments and conclusions
• Identifying
implications of arguments
• Identifying
Assumptions
• Evaluating
the truth of reasons and assumptions
• Evaluating
support for conclusions
Identifying Arguments and Conclusions
• To
identify reasoning, we need to look for indicator words in the conclusion. Some
indicator words to be sought in the concluding statement are “should,” “must,”
“it is evident,” “obviously,” “so,” “thus,” “hence” and “therefore.” Example:
“He must be older than 42; he has a daughter who is 39 years old.”
• When
indicator words are absent, look for relationship between statements in a
passage. Example: Knowing the dangers of smoking is not sufficient to stop
people from smoking. Everybody knows that smoking causes lung cancer and heart
disease. One third of the population still smokes.
• When
there is no conclusion in the passage, then it does not contain an argument.
Identifying Implications of Arguments
• This
involves either of the two skills: parallel arguments and applying principles.
Parallel arguments from a known domain help us to find the flaw in the
argument. Applying principles calls for consistency in reasoning and its
consequence in all similar situations.
• The
argument is faulty if an example from a known domain with parallel structures
of argument can be shown to be faulty. Example:
o Original
argument: We have all had the experience of being deceived by our senses – the
stick which looks bent when it is straight – and all the information we get
through our senses is potentially illusory, therefore sense experience is
always unreliable.
o Parallel
argument: We have all had the experience of being lied to – that even lovers
lie – and that everyone is potentially a liar, therefore no one is trustworthy.
• Application
of principles to other cases may show us that the principle needs to be
modified or rejected. Example: “Killing is wrong.” this principle implies that
the killing in self-defense is wrong. If we are convinced that killing in
self-defense is not wrong then the original principle has to undergo
modification.
Identifying Assumptions
• There
are two types of assumptions: Assumptions underlying basic reasons and
Assumptions as unstated conclusion.
• Assumptions
underlying basic reasons: The reason provided for an argument is based on an
assumption, that is, no empirical study or any study beyond disproof as has
established this as a fact. Example: The number of accidents will reduce when
strict measures of penalties and punishments are deployed by the government.
The underlying assumption is better enforcement of law is directly related to
the decrease in the number of accidents. Without any proof, this claim that the
reason for the high number of accidents is lack of proper enforcement of law.
• Assumptions
as unstated conclusions: A conclusion based on potentially disputable premises
can be called assumptions as unstated consequences. Example: the burglar must
have left by the fire escape. This person is not in the building now, but has not
been seen leaving the building, and there are guards posted at each entrance.
The conclusion is that the burglar must have left the fireplace, but the
premises are still disputable. It is likely that the guards were not
sufficiently watchful.
Evaluating the Truth of Reasons and Assumptions
• The
authority of the person in the subject in question
• Factors
that can possibly distort the accuracy of the person’s judgments
• Other
sources either corroborating or contradicting the person’s position.
Evaluating Support for Conclusions
• Every
conclusion is supported by reason or reasons. Conclusion may state a supposed
fact (it is dangerous to drive a car after drinking alcohol) or make a
recommendation (you ought not to drive your car). Some arguments introduce
their conclusion with “so” or “therefore.” A conclusion need not be the last
statement in the argument. Example: “You have to take a Happitum travel
sickness pill when you go on the ferry. They are very effective against
sea-sickness, and you have always been sick in the past when you have travelled
by sea.”
• One
way of identifying faulty reasoning is through the use of the principle “some
does not imply all.” Example: Some people say that the depiction of violence on
television has no effect on viewers' behaviour. However, if what was shown on
television did not affect behaviour, television advertising would never
influence viewers to buy certain products. But we know that it does. So it
cannot be true that television violence does not affect behaviour. Faulty
reasoning: The fact that advertising shown on television affects viewers’
behaviour is not a good reason for accepting that everything on television
affects viewers’ behaviour.
• Another
way of identifying faulty reasoning is the lack of sufficient evidence. If
people became healthier as the affluence of the country increased, we would
expect the population to be healthier now than it was thirty years ago. But
over the last thirty years new illnesses, such as chronic fatigue syndrome,
have appeared, and we have become more vulnerable to old diseases such as heart
disease and cancer. So the increased wealth of the country has not produced
improvement in the health of the population. Faulty reasoning: Even if some new
diseases have appeared and old diseases have become more common during the last
thirty years, it does not follow that the population is less healthy than it
was thirty years ago, because people may have long periods of good health
before suffering from these diseases.
• A
third way of identifying faulty reasoning is by verifying if correlation is
equated with cause. In the above stated example, claiming that increased
affluence had produced an improvement in the health of the population, the
argument has flawed because it assured that because two things have occurred
together, one has caused the other, and because it failed to consider other
possible causes of the improvements in the health of the population.
MAKING AN OUTLINE
Preliminary Remarks
• After
the notes are taken carefully, read them to get a bird’s-eye view of the
material. Then, as a first step towards writing the paper, prepare an outline.
• Include
the important questions you want to address and the main divisions you want to
make. This helps avoiding materials that, though interesting, are irrelevant to
your paper, but also focus on materials that are relevant.
• The
outline divides the points into various groups, co-ordinates the main points,
subordinates the sub-points, and discards trivia.
• Look
for a general structure. Arrange your ideas and notes according to this
structure, looking for order, progress, and forcefulness.
Illogical versus Logical Coordination
• Take
care to avoid illogical coordination. This can be done by coordinating items
only of the same logical category.
• The
following gives the examples both of improper and proper coordination:
Illogical
Sartre
Existentialism
Phenomenology
Derrida Logical
Husserl
Heidegger
Levinas
Derrida
Improper versus Proper Subordination
• Avoid
improper subordination. Improper subordination consists in placing a topic
under the wrong heading or putting a main point in a subordinate position.
• The
following gives the examples both of improper and proper subordination:
Improper
Schools of Thought
Existentialism
Phenomenology
Ferdinand de Saussure
Proper
Schools of Thought
Existentialism
Phenomenology
Structuralism
Subdivision
• Avoid
single subdivision. To divide you always need at least two parts. This means,
there can never be an “A” without a “B,” a “1” without “2,” an “a” without a
“b.” For an enumeration having several subdivisions, one of the following
schemes or notation and indentation could be used.
• Scheme
1
I. Main heading
A.
Subheading (level 1)
1.
Subheading (level 2)
a.
Subheading (level 3)
i. Subheading (level 4)
ii. Subheading (level 4)
b.
Subheading (level 3)
1.
Subheading (level 2)
B.
Subheading (level 1)
II. Main heading
• Scheme
2
1. Title
1.1
Subtitle
1.1.1
Subtitle
1.1.2
Subtitle
1.2
Subtitle
1.1.1
Subtitle
1.1. 2
Subtitle
1. Title
1.1
Subtitle
1.1.1
Subtitle
1.1.2
Subtitle
1.2
Subtitle
1.3 WRITING
A PAPER
GENERAL
REGULATIONS
Introductory Remarks
• The
paper must be clear, concise, accurate, well organized, and neat.
• To
achieve these, pay attention to the size and quality of the paper, the format,
the language, and the style.
• Print
out dissertation on standard-sized white paper (A4).
• As
a general rule, use 1.5 line space) throughout the paper, except footnotes,
bibliography and indented quotations.
• Set
the margins of your document to 1 inch on all sides. If it is a long thesis,
increase the left margin by ½ inch.
• Keep
in mind your reader. Imagine that you are writing for a fellow student who is
familiar with your discipline but does not know your area.
• Use
simple wording, short paragraphs, and active voice, if possible.
• Vary
sentence lengths.
• Use
gender-neutral or inclusive language, avoiding such gimmicks as using he/she,
but recasting sentences to achieve invisible gender neutrality.
• Avoid
negatives, especially double negatives. Write, for example, uncommon instead of
not common and known instead of not unknown.
• Place
sequences in order (Avoid: “Before giving our critical comments, we shall
discuss the salient features of Derrida’s deconstruction.” Say: “We shall
discuss the salient features of Derrida’s deconstruction before giving our
critical comments.”
Indentation
• Indent
the first line of paragraphs.
• Indent
the footnotes five spaces form the left-hand margin.
• Items
in the Reference/Works Cited list use hanging indent, i.e., they have first
line with the left-hand margin while the following lines are indented five
spaces (or 0.5”).
• Long
quotations (more than 5 typed lines) are indented spaces (or 0.5”) either only
in the left or on both sides without quotation marks.
Pagination
• Short
Paper: Using Arabic numerals, number all pages including the title page. You
may choose not to show the page number on the title page (first page).
• Long
Dissertation: All pages before the first page of Introduction one are numbered
in small roman numerals (i, ii, iii, etc.). Beginning from the first page of
Introduction, all pages have Arabic numbers consecutively to the end of the
paper, including bibliography and appendixes.
• For
both short papers and long dissertations, numbers are placed uniformly either
at the top right, or at the bottom right, or at the bottom center of the page.
Label Visuals
• Label
each visual (i.e., tables, figures, etc.) with an Arabic numeral (Table 1,
Figure 1, and so on) and provide a clear title that identifies the subject.
• For
each table, the label and title should appear on the same line above the table.
• For
each figure, place the label and the caption on the same line below the figure.
The word “Figure” may be abbreviated to “Fig.”
• If
there is a source for the table or the figure, you may either give a footnote
at the end of the title/caption or you may choose to mention the source
directly below the table or the figure.
STEPS IN WRITING
First Draft
• Follow
your outline and write the full text carefully.
• Do
not copy long quotations, but note their place in the paper and mark the
reference.
• Keep
writing without searching for the perfect word or phrase, but pay attention to
the logic and the coherence of thought.
• Incorporate
good passages from other writers.
• Limit
your scope and exclude everything irrelevant.
• Show
this draft, prepared in double-space, to your guide or friends for comments and
criticism.
Second Draft
• Respond
to criticisms and incorporate suggestions and corrections.
• Look
for the appropriate words/phrases and accurate expressions, using a thesaurus.
• Add
emphasis to important points and avoid irrelevant and unimportant materials.
• Show
this copy, typed in double-space, to your guide to get further suggestions and
corrections.
Final Draft
• Once
again, answer criticisms and incorporate suggestions and corrections.
• Improve
accuracy, clarity, forcefulness and readability.
• Change
language style by using simpler wording, shorter sentences and paragraphs,
active rather than passive voice, substituting positives for negatives, writing
sequences in order.
• Prepare
a precise introduction and a well thought out conclusion.
• Prepare
a list of reference, appendix and index before generating the table of
contents.
• Prepare
a title page in the prescribed scientific format.
• Proofread
your paper. Check spelling grammar, punctuation and the logical development of
ideas. Go through carefully the citations, foot-notes and the reference.
• Submit
the final draft to your guide and incorporate his/her suggestions for the
improvisation of your paper.
1.4 THE
MAIN DIVISIONS OF A PAPER
Overview
• Your
paper may not have all these divisions, but whatever parts it has, will follow
in this order: Title Page, Acknowledgement, Table of Contents, Introduction,
Main Body of the Text, Conclusion, Reference, Appendix, Index
Title Page for a Short Paper
• Do
not make a title page for a short paper unless specifically requested.
• In
the top left corner of the first page list your name, roll number, your
instructor’s name, the course name followed by the code, and the date (only
month and year). Do not use any punctuation after any of these entries.
• Begin
your paper immediately after these entries with your title and subtitle (if
there is one) centered and the title bolded.
• Do
not use any punctuation mark after the title. A question mark or an exclamation
mark may be used after the title only when necessary and appropriate.
• Begin
pagination from the first page though you may choose to make the page number
invisible on this page.
Sample First Page for a Short paper
Rahul Gupta
09021
Dr. Nishant A. Irudayadason
PH 14 Hermeneutics
December 2010
Understanding as a Mode of Being
The Significance of Heidegger’s Ontological
Hermeneutics
With
the publication of Heidegger’s Being and Time, the scope of hermeneutics has
gone beyond Schleiermacher and Dilthey. While for Schleiermacher, hermeneutics
is primarily an art of divining the mind of the author…
Title Page for a Long Dissertation
• Make
the separate title page for a long paper (dissertation or thesis having chapter
divisions) and arrange the entries centered between margins in the following
order.
o The
main title of your paper followed by the subtitle, if any (Only the main title
may be capitalized and bolded).
o Your
name followed by your roll number
o Your
Guide’s name prefixed by his designation
o The
purpose of the paper
o The
date of submission (only the month and the year)
o The
name of the institution followed by the name of the city (with pin code)
• The
line spacing shall be set for 1.5 for the entire title page. Between each entry
give 5 space by giving the enter command on the keyboard.
• Keep
the same font type and size as in the body the paper.
• As
a rule the first letter of all the words in the title page will be in capitals
except if the word is an article or a preposition.
Acknowledgement
• Acknowledgement
normally follows the title page and precedes the table of contents.
• The
page number on this page shall follow the page number of the title page in
Roman numerals.
• Avoid
exaggeration and flowery words.
• Make
sure to acknowledge your thesis guide, other professors and the library staff.
• You
may also include your family, friends, bishop/superior, community where you
live, etc. in the order that seems most appropriate for you.
Table of Contents
• It
should include all divisions that precede it and follow it except the title
page.
• Roman
small numerals are given for the divisions that precede it and Arabic numerals
are given to divisions that follow it.
• It
can be generated automatically in MS Word. In order to do so, the different
levels are headings are to be defined correctly.
• Generate
the Table of Contents only just before taking the print of the final copy
because any change made after may result in the indication of wrong page
numbers.
• Before
taking the print out, type in title case “Table of Contents” or merely
“Contents,” and center this heading.
Introduction
• Introduction
is written after having completed the body of the text.
• It
introduces the topic undertaken for the study and spells out the reason for
undertaking this study.
• It
will also speak of the different methods employed for the study.
• It
will seek to justify why the chapters are divided the way they are divided,
thus offering a justification for thematic coherence.
• If
it is a long dissertation the Introduction will run through a few pages.
• The
page number in Arabic numerals begins with the first page of the Introduction,
which will continue till the last page of the paper.
Main Body of the Text
• The
text should contain everything necessary for a reader to understand the
author’s views.
• Longer
papers (dissertation or thesis) are divided into numbered chapters.
• Begin
each chapter on a new page.
• The
length of the chapter may vary as each chapter is a thematically unity.
• Short
titles are preferable. The title of the chapters should bring out the theme.
Center the title of the chapter below the chapter number.
• It
is preferable not to have more than three levels of subtitles.
• Do
not use full stop, comma or semicolon after titles or subtitles. A colon may be
used to separate the subtitle form the title. Use an exclamation mark or
question mark if the title requires it.
Use of
Numerals
• Spell
out numbers written in one or two words and represent other numbers by numerals
(one, thirty-two, fifteen hundred, two million, but 2 1/2; 102, 275).
• Spell
out the number if the sentences begin with a number.
• Fractions
and compound numbers below one hundred should be hyphenated (one-third,
thirty-six).
• For
large numbers you may use a combination of numerals and words (4.5 million, 2
trillion).
• Express
related numbers in the same style (5 of the 250 delegates; from 1 billion to
1.2 billion; 115 feet by 90 feet (or 115’x 90’) but not five out of 250
delegates; one billion to 1.2 billion.
• If
you project calls for frequent use of numbers (a paper on scientific matters or
a paper involving statistics), use numerals for all numbers connected with
statistics or scientific data.
• Always
use numerals for the following:
o With
abbreviations or symbols (6 lbs., 4:29 p.m. (or P.M.), $9, 3%, 4”)
o In
address ( 201 lattice bridge road)
o In
dates (1 April 1993)
o In
decimal fractions (3.5, 7.8)
o In
page or volume references (page 16, volume 6).
• Numbers
and letters occurring in enumeration in the text are enclosed in parentheses.
For example, (1), (a). When each item in an enumeration begins a new line or
paragraph, numerals or letters may be followed by a right parenthesis. For
example, 11)
• For
an enumeration without subdivisions, Arabic numerals followed by full stops are
preferred; the full stops are always aligned.
• Use
capitals of roman numerals for individuals in a series (Henry VI, Pope Benedict
XVI).
• Large
round numbers may be written as follows: Four billion dollars (or $4 billion);
16, 500, 000 (or 16.5million.)
• Regardless
of the original source, numbers referring to the following are given in Arabic
Numerals:
o Pages
o Divisions
of a book (Volume, Parts, Chapters, Act, Scene)
o Illustrations,
tables, or figures
• In
documentation you may use appropriate abbreviations for the divisions of the
book (p. 30, vol. 2, Ch. 5, Fig. 3).
• In
footnotes, indexes, etc., where page range is to be shown, follow the
convention given below:
o Full
numbers to be given for numbers through 99 (p. 78-83).
o For
larger numbers, give only the last two figures if it is in the same hundred
(pp. 102-10; 1997-98).
o If
it is in another hundred, add more figures as needed (1497-506; 1996-2003).
• Use
a combination of figures and words for numbers when such a combination will
keep you writing clear:
o Unclear:
The club celebrated the birthdays of 6 90yrs- olds who were born in the city.
(This may cause the reader to read 690 as one number.)
o Clear:
The club celebrated the birthdays of six 90-year- olds who were born in the
city.
• Regarding
the use of date, there are differences between British and American English.
• The
following table shows some typical formats. Whichever format you choose, be
consistent.
• The
common way of referring to years is as follows: 1066 CE, 1900 BCE, 1971-72 or
1971-1972, the eighties or the 1980’s or the 1980s.
• Spell
out centuries in lower case letters (twentieth century). Hyphenate if it is
used as an adjective (twentieth-century thought nineteenth and
twentieth-century writings).
• Time
may be written as follows: 8:00 AM (or a.m.); eight o’clock in the morning;
4:30 PM (or p.m.); half-past four in the afternoon; 12:00 noon; 12:00 midnight.
• Residence
numbers in addresses are written thus: 16 Tenth Street; 350 West Street.
• In
abbreviating, always use accepted forms. In appropriate contexts, you may
abbreviate, keeping in mind clarity. Spell out the term if the abbreviation may
puzzle the readers.
Conclusion
• In
a long dissertation, the conclusion will run through a few pages.
• It
highlights the finding of your study, relating to the questions you have raised
in your introduction.
• It
also specifies other issues resulted from your study, which open up the
possibility for further research.
• Though
it brings together the loose ends of the paper, it is not meant to be a summary
of the preceding chapters.
• Finally,
the conclusion is not conclusive. This means that you do not seek to offer
dogmatic proofs to the question(s) under investigation. Nor do you pretend that
you have resolved the issue once and for all. Protect yourself from
intellectual dogmatism.
Reference
• Reference
should contain all the cited either directly quoting a passage or giving a
summary idea of the work. It does not include works related to the subject
matter, which you have not made use of.
• It
is usually arranged in alphabetical order according to the surname (last name)
of the author.
• If
your study is author-based, then you may divide your reference into Primary
Sources (referring to the works of the author) and Secondary Sources.
• No
other classification such as books, articles, etc., is allowed.
• Encyclopaedia
and dictionaries do not feature in the reference.
• Religious
books like Bible, Koran and Bhagavad-gita are not included in the reference
unless the study is made on a section of these religious works and you want to
mention the different versions and translations you have made use of in your
study.
Appendix
• An
appendix may include explanations and elaborations that are not essential parts
of the text, but helpful to the reader.
• This
may include the following:
o Documents
o Survey
questionnaires
o Charts
o Tables
o Illustrations
o Images
Index
• The
index begins on a recto (i.e., page on the right side of an open book).
• If
there are both name and subject indexes, the name index precedes the subject
index.
• Indexes
are normally set two columns to a page and in smaller type than the text.
1.5 WRITING BIBLIOGRAPHY IN TURABIAN AND APA
STYLES
Here we deal with two main styles for taking
bibliography which is a must for any academic articles or books. "Turabian
style" is named after the book's original author, Kate L. Turabian, who
developed it for the University of Chicago. Except for a few minor differences,
Turabian style is the same as The Chicago Manual of Style. However, while The
Chicago Manual of Style focuses on providing guidelines for publishing in
general, Turabian's Manual for Writers of Research Papers, Theses, and
Dissertations focuses on providing guidelines for student papers, theses and
dissertations.
American Psychological Association (APA) Style is a
set of rules developed to assist reading comprehension in the social and
behavioral sciences. Designed to ensure clarity of communication, the rules are
designed to "move the idea forward with a minimum of distraction and a
maximum of precision." It is the most often used style in science.
Introductory Remarks
• Typically
Chicago papers include a bibliography, an alphabetically arranged list of cited
or consulted works. This list should not include books that have not seen or
consulted, just to make an impression.
• Start
the bibliography on a new page, and center the title “Bibliography” about one
inch from the top of the page. Number the bibliography pages consecutively with
the rest of the paper.
• Invert
the name of the authors (last name followed by first), and alphabetize the
bibliography by the last names of the authors (or editors, compilers, or
translators). When a work has no author or editor, alphabetize by the first
word of the title other than the articles a, an, or the.
Book: Single Author
• A
single-author entry precedes a multi author entry beginning with same name.
Turabian
Borradori, Giovanna. Philosophy in a Time of Terror.
Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2003.
American Psychological Association
Borradori, G. (2003). Philosophy in a Time of
Terror. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Book: Many Authors
• In
a double-author entry, only the first author’s name is inverted (Coleman, A.E.;
Coleman, A.E. and Richard Northwood).
Turabian
Kofman, Amy Ziering and Kirby Dick. Derrida. New
York: Zeitgeist Video, 2003.
American Psychological Association
Kofman, A. Z., & Dick, K. (2003). Derrida. New
York: Zeitgeist Video.
One Author and One Translator
Turabian
Bataille, Georges. Inner Experience. Translated by
Leslie-Anne Boldt. New York: SUNY Books, 1988.
American Psychological Association
Bataille, G. (1988). Inner Experience. (Leslie-Anne
Boldt. Trans.). New York: SUNY Books. (Original work published 1943).
One Author and
Many Translators
Turabian
Derrida, Jacques. Memoires: For Paul de Man.
Translated by Cecile Lindsay, Jonathan Culler and Eduaro Cadava. New York:
Columbia University Press, 1989.
American Psychological Association
Derrida, J. (1989). Memoires: For Paul de Man, (C.
Lindsay, J. Culler & E. Cadava, Trans.). New York: Columbia University
Press. (Original work published 1988).
One Author One Editor
Turabian
Derrida, Jacques. Acts of Religion. Edited by Gil
Anidjar. London: Routledge, 2001.
American Psychological Association
Derrida, J. (2001). Acts of Religion. G. Anidjar,
(Ed.). London: Routledge.
Editor or Compiler as Author
Turabian
Harvey, Irene, ed. The Purloined Poe: Lacan,
Derrida, and Psychoanalytic Reading. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press,
1988.
American Psychological Association
Harvey, I. (Ed.). (1988). The Purloined Poe: Lacan,
Derrida, and Psychoanalytic Reading.Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.
Single Author: Essay/Article in an Edited Work
Turabian
Bennington, Geoffrey. “Mosaic Fragment, if Derrida
were an Egyptian,” in Derrida: A Critical Reader. Edited by David Wood, 97-139.
Massachusetts: Blackwell, 1991.
American Psychological Association
Bennington, G. (1992). Mosaic Fragment, if Derrida
were an Egyptian. In David Wood (Ed.), Derrida: A Critical Reader (97-139).
Massachusetts: Blackwell.
Article in a Journal
Turabian
Abrams, Meyer H. “The Deconstructive Angel,”
Critical Inquiry 3 (December 1977): 425-438.
American Psychological Association
Abrams, M. H. (1977). The Deconstructive Angel.
Critical Inquiry, 3, 425-438.
1.6 SAMPLE
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Attridge, Derek. (ed.). Derrida: Acts of Literature,
New York: Routledge, 1991.
Caputo, John D. Deconstruction in a Nutshell, New
York: Fordham University Press, 1997.
Caputo, John D. The Prayers and Tears of Jacques
Derrida, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997.
Critchley, Simon. The Ethics of Deconstruction:
Derrida and Levinas, Oxford: Blackwell, 1991.
Culler, Jonathan. On Deconstruction: Theory and
Criticism after Structuralism, New York: Cornell University Press, 1983.
Derrida, Jacques. Adieu à Emmanuel Lévinas, Paris:
Galilée, 1997.
_____. Donner la mort, Paris: Galilée, 1999.
_____. “Différance,” trans. Alan Bass, in Critical
Theory since 1965, ed. Hazard Adams & Leroy Searle Tallahassee: Florida
State University Press, 1986.
_____. “Plato’s Pharmacy,” in Dissemination, trans.
Barbara Johnson, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981.
_____. Margins of Philosophy, trans. Alan Bass,
Chigago: University of Chicago Press, 1981.
_____. Of Grammatology, trans.
GayatriChakravortySpivak, Baltimore: John Hopkins University press, 1976.
_____. Positions, trans. Alan Bass, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1981.
_____. Specters of Marx, trans. PaggyKamuf, New
York: Routledge, 1994.
_____. Speech and Phenomena, trans. David B.
Allison, Evanston: North-western University Press, 1973.
_____. “Hospitality, Justice, and Responsibility: A
Dialogue with Jacques Derrida,” in Questioning Ethics: Contemporary Debates in
Philosophy, ed. Richard Kearney and Mark Dooley, New York: Routledge, 1999.
Eagleton, Terry. Literary Theory: An Introduction,
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983.
Greisch, Jean. Herméneutique et Grammatologie,
Paris: CNRS, 1977.
Heidegger, Martin. Einführung in die Metaphysik,
Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1966.
Kearney, Richard. “Deconstruction and the Other:
Dialogue with Derrida,” in Dialogue with Contemporary Continental Thinkers: The
Phenomenological Heritage, Manchester: Manchester University press, 1984.
Levinas, Emmanuel. Totalité et infini: Essai sur
l’extériorité, Paris: Kluwer Academic, 1971.
_____. Ethics and Infinity, trans. Richard A. Cohen,
Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1985.
Sarup, Madan. An Introductory Guide to
Post-structuralism and Postmodernism, Athens: University of Georgia Press,
1993.
Wood, David. The Deconstruction of Time, Atlantic
Highlands: Humanities Press International, 1989.
1.7 LET US SUM UP
In this unit we saw the general guides on writing a
paper and saw the main divisions of a paper. Then we took up the issue of
writing a bibliography, specifically using Turabian and APA styles.
1.8 KEY WORDS
APA: American Psychological Association (APA) Style
is a set of rules developed to assist reading comprehension in the social and
behavioral sciences. Designed to ensure clarity of communication, the rules are
designed to "move the idea forward with a minimum of distraction and a
maximum of precision." It is the most often used style in science.
Recto: A right-hand page of a book or the front side
of a leaf, on the other side of the verso.
UNIT 2 METHOD OF FOOTNOTES
Contents
2.0 Objectives
2.1 Introduction
2.2 Citations and Notes
2.3 General Hints for Footnotes
2.4 Writing Footnotes
2.5 Examples of Footnote or Endnote
2.6 Examples of a Research Article
2.7 Let us Sum up
2.8 Key Words
2.9 Further
Readings and References
2.0 OBJECTIVES
• To
study the main points in taking footnotes or endnotes.
• To
be able to write a scientific paper with proper footnotes and bibliography
2.1 INTRODUCTION
After having seen the method of taking bibliography
in the previous unit, we are in a position to see the main points in writing
footnotes. We begin by making a general distinction between citation, footnotes
and endnotes. Then we proceed to follow the rules to write proper footnotes.
2.2 CITATIONS AND
NOTES
Generally it is said, a citation is a reference to a
published or unpublished source. More precisely, a citation is an abbreviated
alphanumeric expression, e.g.
(Pandikattu 1998), which is embedded in the body of the text that denotes an
entry in the bibliographic references section of the work, in order to
acknowledge the works of other authors. Generally the combination of both the
in-body citation and the bibliographic entry constitutes what is commonly
thought of as a citation. It may be noted that bibliographic entries given at
the end of the text do not constitute citation and acknowledgement of the
sources the author is indebted to. A prime purpose of a citation is
intellectual honesty; to attribute to other authors the ideas they have
previously expressed, rather than give the appearance to the work's readers
that the work's authors are the original
and he or she alone is responsible for the ideas in the book.
The forms of citations generally subscribe to one of
the generally accepted citations systems, such as the Harvard, MLA, American
Sociological Association (ASA), American Psychological Association (APA), and
other citations systems, as their syntactic conventions are widely known and
easily interpreted by readers. Each of these citation systems has its
respective advantages and disadvantages relative to the trade-offs of being
informative (but not too disruptive) and thus should be chosen relative to the
needs of the type of publication being crafted. Editors will often specify the
citation system to use (Wikipedia 2010).
Bibliographies, and other list-like compilations of references, are
generally not considered citations because they do not fulfill the true spirit
of the term: deliberate acknowledgment by other authors of the priority of
one's ideas. Footnotes and Endnotes are
more detailed forms of citations. They are used to give credit to sources of
any material borrowed, summarized or paraphrased. They are intended to refer
readers to the exact pages of the works listed in the Works Cited, References,
or Bibliography section.
The main difference between Footnotes and Endnotes
is that Footnotes are placed numerically at the foot (end) of the very same
page where direct references are made, while Endnotes are placed numerically at
the end of the essay on a separate page entitled Endnotes or Notes. It is much
easier to refer to footnotes, but endnotes does not disturb the smooth flow of
the text in an article. If you are still using a typewriter, a superscript
number is typed half a space above the line after the last word of the
citation, e.g., "The Information Superhighway is giving way to a
Commercial Superhighway."1 If you are using a word processor, you can
access the superscript function. To type a Footnote citation, the same
superscript number is put at the beginning of the Footnote at the bottom of the
same page where the citation occurs. In word process this step is easy, since
it takes place automatically.
When mentioning a work for the first time, a full
and complete Footnote or Endnote entry must be made. When the same work is
mentioned later, the full details need not be repeated.
2.3 GENERAL HINTS
FOR FOOTNOTES
Introductory Remarks
The writer must acknowledge indebtedness to an
author or source, not only for material quoted verbatim, but for every fact,
judgment, theory, or principle taken from other sources. This applies,
therefore, to paraphrase of summary as well. Common facts known to every
intelligent reader need no acknowledgement. Failure to acknowledge the source
is called plagiarism. It invites severe penalties since it amounts to cheating
or robbing. All quotation should correspond exactly with the originals in
wording, spelling and punctuation. Hence there is need for care. No matter how
brief the quotation, the description of the context should usually be given in
order to avoid misleading or unwarranted interpretation of the author quoted.
While quoting, a quotation should never be given a sense different from that which
it had in its original context. For example, it is wrong to say the following:
The Bible says, “There is no God” (Ps 14:1). Quote authors who have something
special to say about the topic under consideration (authors who give a new
theory, express it in a striking way, or raise serious objections). Quote only
the pertinent passages of an author who is an authority in the field.
Second-hand quotations are permissible only if it is impossible to verify them
in the original source.
Format
A quotation can be placed in the text or in the foot
note or in the appendix. It is placed in the text if it is very important for
the paper. It is placed in the footnote if it is merely a confirmation of an
idea in the text. If the author has many passages, only the most appropriate
quote is placed in the test; other passages are cited in the footnote. Footnote
is the appropriate place for the original text whose translation is inserted
into the body of the paper.
General Tips
Quotations, direct or indirect, should be kept to a
minimum lest the paper may give the impression of being a mere compilation of
quotations. A direct quotation must be as brief as possible contain only the
really pertinent matter. A careful paraphrase or an exact summary is better
than a long quotation. Such a paraphrase or summary must not be enclosed in
quotation marks. The number of the footnote is placed at the end of the
paraphrase or summary. Do not simply drop quotations into your paper and leave
it to the reader to make connections. You must integrate the quotation into the
paper with the help of signals, assertions and connections. Example: Ross, in
her study of working-class women (signal), makes it clear that economic status
determined the meaning of motherhood (assertion). Among this population
(connection), “to mother was to work for and organize household subsistence.”
Short Quotations
If the quotation is short (fewer than one hundred
words or approximately five typed lines of prose), enclose it within double
quotation marks and incorporate it into your text. When a brief incorporated
quotation ends a sentence in the text, it is always followed by a full stop. If
a brief quotation is used within a sentence, the original punctuation is
replaced by the punctuation proper to the sentence.
Long Quotations
Use long quotations only when it is necessary to do
so. The long quotations are not enclosed in double quotation marks, but
indented. If there is double quotation in the original source, convert it into
single quotation mark if it is a brief quotation, but maintain the double
quotation marks if it is a long quotation. If you are using the author-date
format instead of foot-note, provide the surname of the author, followed by a
colon, a space and the specific page. If you are giving footnotes to the citations,
instead of the parenthetical citation, provide the superscript number in the
text and complete reference in the footnotes. In quotations form works in
foreign languages, it is helpful and advisable to give a translation, at least
in the footnotes.
Ellipsis
The omission of words or sentences within a
quotation is always indicated by ellipsis. For an ellipsis within a sentence,
use three dots placed in square brackets […]. If there are ellipsis marks in
the quoted author’s work, do not put brackets around them; brackets around
ellipsis marks are meant to distinguish the ellipsis you added form the
ellipsis marks in the quoted author’s work. Do not use ellipsis (…) to begin an
indented quotation. However, while quoting many paragraphs, if words are omitted
at the beginning of paragraphs other than the first, indicate the omission
using ellipsis after the paragraph indentation. The omission of one complete
paragraph or more in a prose quotation or of a line or more in a verse
quotation should be indicated by a single line of spaced full stops. Enclose
any foreign matter (change, addition, correction or personal comment) inserted
into a direct quotation with brackets, i.e. [ ], not parentheses, i.e., () to
indicate that it is not part of the original text. If some words required for
easy reading are missing, insert them in brackets at the appropriate place.
Punctuation
The comma and the full stop are always placed inside
the quotation marks, whether they are part of the quotation or not. The colon
and semicolon are always placed outside the quotation marks. The exclamation
mark or the question mark is placed inside the quotation marks when it is part
of the quoted matter; otherwise, outside. Example: Does he precisely show “evil
leading somehow to good”? The question asked was: “Can evil ever lead to good?”
Indicating Errors
in the Original
Do not make corrections to the original text you are
quoting even if the mistakes are evident.
An evident error (in spelling, grammar, logic) in
the original is pointed out by enclosing sic (thus used) in brackets
immediately after the error (sic). This is to assure the reader that the faulty
spelling or logic was in the original.
Use of Capitals
and Italics
The first word of a quotation is not capitalized if
it is related grammatically to what precedes, even though in the original it
begins a sentence (The Psalmist’s call to “taste and see that the Lord is
good”). This rule should be followed for both kinds of quotations, i.e.,
continuous with text or set off. If the quotation starts after introductory, do
not capitalize the first word. This is applicable even to block quotations.
Words not italicized in the original may be italicized for emphasis. This
change may be indicated to the reader by a notation enclosed in brackets placed
immediately after the italicized words or in the foot note. Example: “I am not
(italics added) one of the desk-pounding types that like to stick out his
jaws.”
2.4 WRITING FOOTNOTES
The following points are discussed in this section:
FOOTNOTES IN CHICAGO STYLE
Introductory Remarks, The research paper will have
to be well documented. Proper documentation saves the researcher from the
accusation of plagiarism, and the consequent penalties.
Frequently Used Abbreviations in Documentation
cf. = confer, compare
vol. = volume
Ibid. = ibidem, in the same place (it is better to avoid it)
Trans. = translated by, translator.
n.d. = no date.
n.p. = no publisher, no place
ms. = manuscripts.
ed. = edition, edited by, editor
ch. Or chap. = chapter
Acknowledging the
Sources
To acknowledge a source in a paper, place a
superscript number immediately after the end of a sentence containing the
quotation, paraphrase, or summary. If a single paragraph of your paper contains
several references to the same author, it is permissible to use one number
after the last quotation, paraphrase, or summary to indicate the source for all
of the material used in that paragraph. Place notes at the bottom of each page,
separated from the text with a typed line, 1.5 inches long. Indent the first
line of each entry one-half inch (or five spaces) from the left margin; do not
indent additional lines an entry. Begin the note with the Arabic numeral.
Footnotes should be numbered consecutively, beginning with 1, either throughout
the chapter or the work.
Format
Author’s first name and then last name.
Full title of the work with subtitles, if any.
Location of publication, publisher, and the year of
publication in parentheses.
Page(s) from which information is taken, avoiding
the abbreviations “p.” and “pp.” before page numbers.
Use commas to separate items.
__________________
1.
Roger Fisher, Getting to Yes: Negotiating Agreement without Giving in (New
York: Penguin Books, 1965), 85.
The first time to cite a source, the note should
include publication information for that work as well as the page number on
which the passage being cited may be found. After the first citation, for
subsequent references to a source to have already cited, give only the author's
last name, a short form of the title, and the page or pages cited. The short
form of the title of a book is italicized; the short form of the title of an
article is put in quotation makes. Use commas to separate items. For example:
__________________
3.
Fisher, Getting to Yes, 31.
If the subsequent references follow immediately
after reference, use the abbreviation “Ibid.” Ibid means “same as above.” It is
used only when the note is form the same source as the one directly above. A
page number is included if the second reference is form the same source as the
one directly above, but the page form which it is taken is different from the
first. For example:
__________________
3.
Fisher, Getting to Yes, 31.
4.
Ibid.
10.
Ibid., 62.
In the author-date system, sources are cited in the
text, usually in parenthesis. It includes the author’s last (family) name, the
year of publication of the work, and a page number (Cox 1997, 166). Full
details appear in the bibliography usually titled “References” or “Works
Cited.”
2.5 EXAMPLES
OF FOOTNOTE OR ENDNOTE
2. G.
Wayne Miller, King of Hearts: The True Story of the Maverick Who Pioneered Open
Heart Surgery (New York: Times, 2000) 245.
Bibliography example:
Miller, G. Wayne. King of Hearts: The True Story of
the Maverick Who Pioneered Open
Heart Surgery. New York: Times, 2000.
Use of ibid. and op. cit.:
Gibaldi does
NOT recommend the use of these old-fashioned abbreviations: ibid. (from the
Latin ibidem meaning "in the same place") and op. cit. (from the
Latin opere citato meaning "in the work cited.")
For Footnote or Endnote citations, if you should see
the term ibid. being used, it just means that the citation is for the second
mention of the same work with no intervening entries:
3 Ibid. 12-15.
More commonly, author and page number or numbers are
now used instead of ibid., e.g.:
4 Miller 12-15.
For second or later mention of the same work with
intervening entries, where previously op. cit. was used, now only the author
and page number or numbers are used:
5 Miller 198.
Use of Superscript
[Tab] or indent Footnote and Endnote entries 5
spaces from the left margin. Leave one space between the superscript number and
the entry. Do not indent second and subsequent lines. Double-space between
entries. Number Footnotes and Endnotes consecutively using a superscript, e.g.,
7.
For Endnotes, you must use the same superscript
number (as in your text) at the beginning of each Endnote in your Endnotes
list. Start your list of Endnotes on a new page at the end of your essay.
Remember to put the Endnotes page before the Bibliography, or Works Cited, or
References page.
Examples of first Footnotes or Endnotes, subsequent
Footnotes or Endnotes, and listings on Works Cited or References page:
Reference from the Bible, Catechism, or Sacred
Texts:
Example in text:
An interesting reference was made to the picking of
corn on the Sabbath.8
Example of Footnote citation, long form:
8 Matthew 12:1-8.
Example of Footnote citation, short form:
8 Mt 12:1-8.
List under Works Cited:
The New Jerusalem Bible: Reader's Edition. New York:
Doubleday, 1990.
Example in text:
The Catechism of the Catholic Church states that
"Because of its common origin the human race forms a unity, for 'from one
ancestor [God] made all nations to inhabit the whole earth.'"9
Example of a first Footnote or Endnote citation for
the above quote from Catechism of the Catholic Church, Part I, Section 2,
Chapter 1, Article 1, Paragraph 6I, Reference #360, Page 103, would be:
9 Catechism of the Catholic Church (New York:
Doubleday, 1994) 360.
Subsequent citation of this same quote:
10 Catechism 360.
Citation of a different quote from the same book:
11 Catechism 1499.
List under Works Cited:
Catechism of the Catholic Church. New York:
Doubleday, 1994.
Examples of Footnote or Endnote citations for other
sacred texts:
12 Pius XII, encyclical, Summi Pontificatus 3.
13 Roman Catechism I, 10, 24.
Do not confuse Footnote and Endnote citations with
explanatory Notes that some authors refer to as "Endnotes." These
Notes are not considered to be citations but are used to add comments,
explanations, or additional information relating to specific passages in the
text.
Internet Sources:
In internet citations, there may be two dates found.
First date = Web page creation or modification date, if it is available. Second
date = the date you accessed the Web page. If the Web page does not have a
modification or creation date, leave it out, but always indicate our access
date of the URL (Lee 2010).
19
Canada, Indian and Northern Affairs, "Aboriginal Peoples Survey: From APS
I to APS II." Facts from Stats, Corporate Information Management
Directorate, Issue No. 15, Mar. 2000,
http://www.inac.gc.ca/nr/nwltr/sts/2000-03_e.html, accessed on 15 Dec. 2004.
19 James
Henretta, et al., "Richard Allen and African-American Identity," America's History, Spring
1997, http://www.earlyamerica.com/review/spring97/allen.html, accessed on 11
Feb. 2006.
19
"Edsitement," http://edsitement.neh.gov, accessed on 12 Feb. 2006.
19 Abdullah
al-Shiri, "Danish Cartoon Prompts Protest," Sunday Herald 29 Jan.
2006, http://ww1.sundayherald.com/53793 accessed on 12 Feb. 2006.
2.6 EXAMPLE OF A
RESEARCH ARTICLE
Physical
Immortality:
Human Longing, Scientific Basis and Religious
Response
Kuruvilla Pandikattu SJ
Jnana-Deepa Vidyapeeth, Pune, India
“The ancient seers were not egoistic. They called
the whole humanity – past, present future – Amrutya putra. You are all sons of
immortality. Equal and eternal.” Bhagawan Rajneesh (Osho 1998: ch3)
“Mankind will postpone human ageing substantially in
the future, doubling the human lifespan at least, when we have accomplished
this we will be ashamed that we did not work on it much sooner.” Michael Rose,
Evolutionary Biogerontologist.
0. Introduction
According to the creation myth of Konos tribes of Guinea, Sa or death existed
before anything. Death is regarded as the primary creator in this tradition.
Once, long time ago, there was only darkness and Sa lived there with his wife
and daughter. Since he wanted something more durable he created a slushy kind
of mud sea as a place to live. From nowhere appeared the god Alatangana and he
decided to improve on the work of Sa. Alatangana made the slush solid and added
animals and plants to it. Sa was pleased and they became friends. But when the
god asked for Sa’s daughter the friendship fell apart. However, Alatangana met
the girl secretly and eloped to a distant place and they produced 14 children:
four white boys, four white girls, three
black boys and three black girls. The children spoke different languages
and the parents could not understand them.
This made them so upset that they decided to return
to Sa and ask for his advice. Sa was
ready to reconcile and demanded that the black and white children do not
intermarry. So the different race originated. Sa demanded further: “You have
stolen my only child. Now you must give me one of yours whenever I wish it.
When I wish to call one of your children I must never be denied. You will know
I am called by the sound of the calabash rattle in your dream.” (Lemming & Lemming 1994: 164) So it was
that death for us humans is the bride-price for Alatangana’s marriage with Sa’s
daughter. So death is intrinsically linked to human’s origin.
This simple myth explains aetiologically both
darkness and life, death and birth, sex and procreation and gives justification
to the races. The main focus of my article is that this intimate link between
death and life may be soon broken – at least in our collective consciousness.
It will have shattering consequences for our human – philosophical and
religious – longing and hope.
In this article I first study the quest for human
physical immortality as a religious search. I see the emerging religious and
collective movements which try to overcome death. In the next section we see
the scientific basis for physical immortality. Though there is no hard
“scientific” evidence for physical immortality, there are so many scientific
disciplines at their cutting-edge or frontier research which indicate at least
the theoretical possibility for physical immortality. In the final part we see
the social or religious response to such a scenario. We shall show that such a
possibility does not negate but radically alters our very understanding and
scope for longing and fulfilment. We conclude by affirming that such a guiding
of our total destiny requires a healthy dialogue between science and society
or technology and religion.
1. Physical Immortality: A Primordial Human Longing
Though the longing for an everlasting life has been
a perennial quest, we are somehow used to our physical death. Since we all take
our mortality for granted, the geronotlogist author Herb Bowie holds that we
tend to ignore the most potent anti-ageing organ in your body – the mind! If
so, then the subconscious messages we are constantly sending ourselves may be
sabotaging human longevity. “Can you imagine yourself living for 100 years,
120, or even longer? If not, then you may be undermining your nutritional
program by feeding yourself ‘mental junk food’ -- negative programming
predicting your own deterioration and demise.”
(Bowie 1999)
The author exhorts that we should start feeding your
mind a new food. His book, Why Die? speaks clearly and intelligently about the possibility
of living virtually forever. By stretching the
mind to accept this exciting new human possibility, we shall be
conditioning ourselves to live a longer,
healthier and happier life.
Most of us make the unconscious decision that we
have to die. They assume that their fate is ordained by the laws of nature, or
by destiny. This choice is made so early in life, and at such an unconscious
level, that few people ever even challenge it. So ask the question on human
immortality will shake people up. Because even to ask this question is to imply
something unthinkable for many people -- that death is a choice, and not a
foregone conclusion. Further, most of us feel disoriented and threatened by the
consideration of physical immortality as a real possibility. It is within these
chilling prospects that the author introduces the concept of physical
immortality.
To understand the idea of living forever, according
to Bowie, we must look at two very different aspects of physical immortality.
On the one hand, it is about eternity, about surviving to some unthinkably
distant point in the future. On the other hand, though, it is all about
choosing how to live our lives today. It is only when we connect these two
extremes, and find a way to live our lives as an unbroken continuum between
these two points, that we fully achieve physical immortality. There is an
element of paradox here.
This paradox is also expressed in these haunting
lines from William Blake.
To see a world in a grain of sand And a heaven in a
wild flower, Hold infinity in the palm of your hand, And eternity in an
hour. (Capra 1977: 288)
I believe that Blake was not speaking metaphorically
though. In the book the author wants to talk about transforming the quality of
our lives today, by focusing our attention on our own eternity. At the same time, I will be talking about
actually living for hundreds and thousands of years, by focusing our attention
on the quality of our lives today. The author asserts that if such a view seems
like a paradox, then this is only because we view our today’s and our
tomorrow’s as separate and unconnected.
Physical immortality is difficult, in a way, to talk
about at length because it can be approached from so many different angles.
Since all of these perspectives are equally valid, it is impossible to do the
subject justice by discussing it in a strictly linear fashion. We can start
with forever and work backwards. We can start with today and go forwards. We
can talk about the fate of humanity, or we can discuss the personal feelings of
one individual. No matter how we approach the subject, though, we always seem
to arrive at the same conclusion: that living forever is a practical and
meaningful goal.
Reaching the same conclusion from so many different
starting points is reassuring in the long run, but can be a bit disconcerting
at first, as we repeatedly shift perspectives. We may feel more comfortable
with some approaches than with others, and so may be tempted to skip around.
Following similar lines of thought, another scholar
claims that the first immortal human beings are living among us today. (Bova 2000) It is asserted by its proponents
that there are men and women alive today who may well be able to live for
centuries, perhaps even extend their life-spans indefinitely. For them, death
will not be inevitable. Death will have
to die for them!
Such immortal humans will not age. They will not
become feeble and sickly. Ageing will be stopped, even reversed. One may be
young and vigorous forever. Accidents
and violence will not disappear, of course. People will still be vulnerable to
poor judgement, bad luck and evildoers. But death from old age, death as the
inescapable end of life, will become a thing of the past, a dark memory of
primitive days. As the American immunologist William R. Clark put it, “Death is
not inextricably intertwined with the definition of life.” Just because human
beings have always died does not mean that they always will die.
This same idea is reflected in the leading article
of the German weekly: Der Spiegel.
(Hanshalter 2000) It asserts that immorality belongs to the originary
human desire (Ursehrsucht). It will not
just redeem humanity from death but raise it almost to the level of gods.
Michael Fossel, professor of Clinical Medicine in the State University of
Michigan asserts: “the most significant turn in the human history has begun. In
twenty years we can stop the process of ageing and reverse biological clock.”
He certainly is a super-optimist. Philipp Lee Miller of the Longevity Institute
in Los Gatos, prophesies: “in a few
years time 80 year olds will feel like 20 year olds and will play like teens.” This sentiment is accentuated by
the New Yorker Professor Michio Kaku,
who expects a tripling of life expectancy and a cessation of ageing process in
a few years time.
The above longings and claims make it abundantly
clear that immortality is slowly distilling into the collective unconsciousness
of humanity. We shall study further the claims of immortality and see if there
is any psychological and scientific basis for it.
[Pages omitted]
5. Conclusion
Such a possibility of human immortality has deep
rooted religious consequence. Religions can
ignore the challenges posed by immortality only at the danger of instant
self mortality. The obvious danger of such a possibility is that each one
becomes so preoccupied with his own individual immortality and forgets the
human community and life in general. There is a danger that the larger issues
of providing justice for the impoverished, fostering of life in general and
love as the most significant human value may be forgotten.
At the same time it must be reiterated that physical
immortality does not render God superfluous, religion redundant and human
longing unnecessary. Even in the situation of immortal humans there is scope
for meaningful hope, for relevant religion and for a liberating God. At the
same time Immortality necessitates a human hope that may be detached from
physical death. In our ordinary understanding of human longing, death is seen
as the starting point of eschatology or
human hope. That view has to be given up and we need to delve deep into the
“inaugurated eschatology” which theologians have taken seriously since few
decades.
We still need to take death seriously. But death may
not be given the supreme importance and inevitability that was it due once. So
the human hope and fulfilment has to begin with this present world, with the
here and now. There are of course social and existential problems like poverty
and injustice which are to be tackled seriously.
It must be noted that overcoming physical death and
attaining physical immortality does not solve the problem of human contingency.
The issue of human finitude has to be
addressed in a much wider sense. The tendency of those seeking physical
immortality – passive acceptance - is to
reduce human life to a physicalistic or mechanistic view point. They would
stress that attainment of physical
immortality – temporal unlimitedness – necessarily leads to human fulfillment.
We need to focus also on the existential and ontological contingency of human
condition, not merely that of the temporal conditioning.
So even in a world of immortal human beings, human
longing and hope is imperative. Hope still remains intrinsic to humans. But it
is a hope based on the day-to-day experience of humans and rooted in the
present day, not one aimed primarily at a later world “a
pie-in-the-sky-when-you-die” type. So life, today’s precious, fragile life, has
to be taken seriously. It has to be
affirmed, respected and fostered in its entirety. We can hope to pay back the bride-price for
Alatangana’s marriage with Sa’s daughter and life lives “full and abundant” and
not necessarily temporally limited.
References
Bowie, Herb, http:
www.powersurgepub.com/books\immort\Bowie why die.htm, 1999. See also URL:
http:// www.sff.net. people.benbova.
Leeming, David and Leeming, Margareth, A Dictionary
of Creation Myths, OUP, New York/Oxford: 1994.
Osho, Bhagavan, Beyond Enlightenment, ch 3, “No
other path but life.” (From CD rom) 1998.
Pandikattu, Kuruvilla (2000) “Significance of God if
humans were to become immortal,” The Month 33 (July 2000): 264-268.
Pandikattu, Kuruvilla, (1999) “Eschatology: Arena for Creative
Encounter between Science and Religion.”
Jeevadhara 29 (April 1999) 154-164.
Spiegel,Der (2000) 17/2000. URL http://www.
spiegel.de/ spiegel/21jh/0,1518, 73761,00.html.
2.7 LET US
SUM UP
In this unit various ways of writing footnotes are
studied, along with their significance in a research article.
2.8 KEY WORDS
Citation: It is a reference to a published or
unpublished source given within the text of an article.
Ellipsis: The
omission of a word or phrase necessary for a complete syntactical construction
but not necessary for understanding
Indentation: The amount of space left between a
margin and the start of an indented line. Also called indent.
UNIT 3 METHOD OF NOTES TAKING
Contents
3.0 Objectives
3.1 Introduction
3.2 Methods
of Note-taking
3.3 Card
Style
3.4 Note
Book Style
3.5 Note
taking in a Computer
3.6 Types
of Note-taking
3.7 Notes
from Field Research
3.8 Errors
to be Avoided
3.9 Let
us Sum up
3.10 Key
Words
3.11 Further
Readings and References
3.0 OBJECTIVES
Research methodology is a system of methods used for
collecting data, information etc. for the solution of problems identified for
research. The central idea of this unit is to bring out the importance of note
taking in the process of research work. Although it is only one among the
different methods while doing research it has enough significance since the
accuracy in taking notes will help us to save a lot of time while preparing the
final report, bibliography etc. The different methods of note taking are also
dealt in this unit. The various types of note taking like summary,
paraphrasing, précis, and quotation are also given importance here. The rules
to be followed in each type of note taking are dealt in detail so that all
methods of note taking and the errors to be avoided are clarified here. Hence
by the end of this unit you will be able to
• have
a basic understanding of note taking method;
• know
about the different methods of note taking;
• understand
different types of note taking;
• make
out the rules to be followed in the different types of note taking;
• know
about the errors to be avoided while taking notes.
3.1 INTRODUCTION
Research is an inquiry carried out scientifically to
discover truth, to draw new conclusion and to bring out new facts. It is the
way to acquire knowledge. According to Advanced Learner’s Dictionary of Current
English, Research is “an investigation undertaken in order to discover new
facts, get additional information etc.” Another definition of research is that
it is “any organised inquiry designed and carried out to provide information
for solving a problem”. Thus it is any activity which helps to gain fresh
insight into something. It is a careful search or inquiry into any subject
matter, which is an endeavour to discover or find out valuable facts which
would be useful for further application or utilisation. The above mentioned
definitions and explanations specify all the major aims of research i.e.,
discovery of new facts, verification and testing of old facts, analysis of
interrelationships and causal explanations and development of new tools,
concepts and theories. A research paper is that in which the conclusions and
findings of such inquiry appear. It is through a research paper that we
communicate our findings of research to others. When we have communicated to
others, the ability to write clear is vital. In order to be meaningful and
clear in communication we should first have a clear cut understanding of the
research problem. Only then we will be able express our self while
communicating it to others. Language used in the paper should always be
concrete and it should be specific.
In order to begin a research work we have to consult
relevant sources of information. The sources of information can be primary or
secondary. The primary sources provide data gathered at first hand and from
which the researcher directly collects data that have not been collected
previously. The secondary sources are those from which data are got at second
hand, that is, sets of data that taken from other people’s original data.
Whereas primary data are first hand information collected through various
methods like observation, interviewing, mailing etc, secondary data are data
which have collected and complied for another purpose. Primary sources include
journal articles, research reports, conference papers, thesis, project reports
etc. Bibliographies, reference books, reviews, directories etc form secondary
sources. The researcher should be capable of sorting out the reliable material
useful for his research work advanced by these sources. After determining the
reliability and usefulness of the sources, we will have to take notes on it. In
this unit, we are making a detail study of the method of notes taking in the
process of research.
3.2 METHOD OF NOTE-TAKING
The clarity in reporting a research work is
influenced by the reader in view, how technical the problem is, the research’s
hold over his facts and techniques, his command over language and the form and
fullness of notes, i.e., of the data and documentation. For keeping accurate
records we need high quality notes and this shows the importance of note-taking
in research. Thus notes taking is an important part while writing a research
paper. This records the information of the sources that we will use while
reporting our research work. Therefore, it is necessary that we should
critically evaluate the texts or articles before we select them and then make
necessary choices before taking notes on them. Otherwise, there is a chance to
overload with information which will be time consuming.
To take effective notes, first of all, we should
understand thoroughly the information contained in the sources. Then notes
should be taken from it so as to develop knowledge and comprehension of the
subject. Thus going through a source, making a decision about what is useful
for a paper and writing notes on it should encourage the researcher to think
more deeply and understand the relevance of the notes taken by him to the
research topic. Again, he should also sort out the material he needs from other
information surrounding it in the text, while taking notes on it. To make use
of this information effectively in the research work, care should be taken to
record it in such a way that it can be easily sorted, reorganised and
incorporated in the paper.
We should take notes in such a way that it briefly
summarizes the most important points of each source. Main points has to be
stressed in the notes and it should be clear and concise as possible. The
details that are unnecessary to the research area should be avoided. It is not
always necessary to write complete sentences or even complete words. We can use
abbreviations which saves a lot of time. But it should be used in such a way
that we can understand them in the notes when we consult it later. One
important thing to be remembered during note taking is that we should always
remember to be record the page number in the text or articles from which our
note is taken. As far as possible, all bibliographical details has to be added
for each source. If possible, we should also try to the review the chapter or
article after note taking so as to make it sure that we have not missed any
important points and also to see that our notes are accurate and complete. The
notes has to be recorded in such a way that we can easily locate all the points
related to a particular subject easily and readily identify the source from
which a piece of information is taken. Thus the requirements of a good not
taking system are as follows: It should facilitate ready location of the
recorded information when required. It should allow flexible handling and
organising of information and All notes related to a particular concept of a
topic should be available together.
There are different methods in taking notes. Some
researchers take notes by hand on index cards or in sheets of paper of a note book. Some
others prefer using a computer to take notes as it will save their time as well
as improve the accuracy in transcribing the material from the sources. While
collecting data by taking notes we should set down first the authors full name
and complete title of the source. By doing this we will be able to locate the
same source easily while working for bibliography.
3.3 CARD
STYLE
If we are taking notes on cards we should record
each piece of information from a source in a separate card. For each source the
completer bibliographical information has to be recorded in one card, which
will be our bibliographical card. Thus this is not only helpful for accuracy
and organisation but also, technically while compiling the bibliography. If we
are taking notes on cards, we should mention the name of the author as usual
and the name of the book is to be
underlined. While taking down the matter, we should leave some margin on the
left side of the card. The card possessing the material from an article from a
book should first mention the name of the author and then the title of the
article in inverted commas with the work cited in underline and the page no:.
If there are two authors, we should mention the name of the first author and
write the other or ‘et al’. For e.g.:
Kootz , Harold, et al, ‘ Management ’
Mc Graw-Hill International Book Company, New Delhi, 1980. p. 120. If the publication is an edited one, we should
use ‘ed ’ after the name.
For multiple notes from the same source, we should
record a short form of the title and author’s last name in the upper right hand
corner of each card. We should always record the page umber from which our
summaries, ideas, paraphrases or direct quotes have been taken in the lower
right hand corner. Materials taken from journal should indicate the name of the
author, title of the article within inverted commas and also the volume and
details of journal along with the page number. For e.g.:-Ananthu, T .S. “Hind
Swaraj- Its Relevance Today.” Gandhi Marg. New Delhi: Gandhi Peace Foundation,
Vol. 31. NO. 2, July- September 2009. Pg
no. 192.
In order to facilitate organising and reorganising
information subject or topic headings on the cards can be written in pencil. To
make note taking on cards more convenient and easy sometimes two sets of cards
are used. One is source cards and the second is known as note cards. Source
cards are used for noting bibliographical information and the note cards are
used for actual note taking. In the source cards bibliographic information
should be recorded in the proper bibliographic format. ‘Author’s name, the
title of the book, the publisher’s name, place and year. On the note cards
information from a printed source is recorded. To make it more flexible , it is
better to note a single fact or an idea on each card and to use only one side
of the card. In the body of the card, first, the name of the author and the
title of the book or article may be noted in order to avoid making any mistake
in identifying the concerned source card. The page number of the source from
which the idea or fact has been taken also is to be noted. Thus, the two sets
of cards together will facilitate in arranging the notes appropriately for
drafting the report.
3.4 NOTE
BOOK STYLE
In this method, we should record all information on
a single page or a series of pages in the note book. We should write all the
bibliographical details including the author, title, place of publication,
publisher and year of publication at the top of the page of each source. Notes
should be recorded in the middle of the page leaving wide margins. In the right
hand margin page numbers of the source from which we have made the notes has to
be recorded. The specific topic to which each piece of information is related
can be noted in the left hand margin . For each source we are consulting , a
new page can be allotted. Notes can be listed according to topic also. But here
care should be taken to list the page numbers because otherwise it will be very
confusing.
3.5 NOTE TAKING IN A COMPUTER
Notes can be entered in a computer and these notes
will be handy. We can enter the notes into a word processor as separate files
in one directory. Otherwise, we can enter all notes in a single file rendering
new name or phrase for each new note. In the first method the needed notes can
be moved to appreciate place in our draft by copying and pasting method. For a
short paper, it is better to opt the computer method and if it is a longer which
makes use of many sources, it is better to opt the cards system because card
system is the most suitable method of note taking. It meets all the
requirements of a good recording system. Cards are tougher and so can withstand
handling. As they are compact, they can be handled easily and can be stored
conveniently in boxes. Also the cards are most flexible while arranging,
rearranging, grouping, and classifying information.
3.6 TYPES
OF NOTE-TAKING
Different types of note-taking include –summary,
paraphrase, quotation and précis.
Summary
If we want only the general idea of a large amounts
of material, it is better to summarise it. This type of note taking describes
and rewrites the source material without specific concern for style and
expression. But it should be done with great care and in this type of note
taking we should try to keep the material as short as possible. Quotation marks
may be provided for key phrase that cannot be paraphrased. Name of the author
and page number also has be mentioned in the note.
Paraphrase
It is restating the material in our own words. As we
have to restate the thought, meaning and attitude of another person in our own
words, paraphrase may be considered as the most difficult type of note taking.
In order to be sound and perfect, in paraphrasing we should try to rewrite the
original in about the same number of words as possible. In text citation may be
provided to the source by mentioning the author and page number in the
paraphrase. Care should be taken while paraphrasing exceptional words and
phrases in the original. It is better to retain by enclosing them within
quotation marks. We should always try to avoid word by word copying as far as
possible in this type of note taking. Paraphrasing will help the researcher to
understand the author’s ideas rather than just mechanically copying them.
Quotation
Direct quotation may be used for documentation of a
major argument where a foot note would not be sufficient and where paraphrasing
the passage might cause misinterpretation. The exact words of an author or the
exact words from an official publication must be quoted. Quotation notes are
necessary because it will enable us to capture opinion of the experts on the
subject. It will also help us to show that we have carried out research in that
area carefully and also to show that there is an authoritative opinion on the
topic we have discussed in the research area. Where a few paragraphs or
sentences are required to be quoted from a quotation which is very long, it is
permissible to omit sections of an original passage by a procedure called
ellipsis. To indicate ellipsis three spaced full stops(---) are inserted. An
ellipsis can occur at the beginning or the end of a quotation. Use double
quotation marks at the beginning and the end of quotation. We should never
forget to acknowledge the quotations by way of a footnote or otherwise.
Other rules to be followed while taking quotation
notes include –
We should always try to quote from primary and
secondary sources.
The quoted material selected should be important and
well phrased
We should always use exact words of the source
If at all possible, we should quote key sentences
and short passages instead of entire paragraphs.
Quotation marks should be used in the notes so as to
distinguish it from summary and paraphrase. If we are downloading a text and
taking quotation from it into our paper, we should always remember to place
quotation marks around the words taken from the source.
Précis
This is quick summary notes. It can be used to
review an article or a book or create an abstract. The original source has to
condensed here with precision and
directness so that the tone of it is preserved. It is better to write the
précis note in our own language but exceptional phrases from the original can
be retained here by enclosing it in quotation marks. Documentation also should
be provided.
3.7 NOTES FROM FIELD RESEARCH
In some instances we will be expected to conduct
field research. This work will require different kinds of notes kept on charts,
cards, notes pads, a research journal, or a computer. If we interview
knowledgeable people, we should make
careful notes during the interviews and transcribe those notes to our draft in
a polished form. If we conduct a questionnaire, the results will become
valuable data for developing notes, graphs and charts for our research paper.
In summarising, paraphrasing, quoting or précis it is important to keep an
accurate record of the pages and other numbered sections. Care should also be
taken to be in a middle way between not taking too much of notes and not
recording too little. We should try to be both thorough and concise. Accuracy
has to be maintained not only in quotations but also in summarising and paraphrasing
the original sources.
Good note taking will help us a lot in avoiding
plagiarism which is the act of taking ideas , passages etc. from an author and
presenting them as one’s own. Writers plagiarise when they present the words or
ideas of others without making it clear that these are not their own words or
ideas. In order to make sure that we have not plagiarised, we should see that
each of the phrase or ideas borrowed from other sources are credited to that
source. Acknowledgement of the source is that which distinguishes a scholar
from a plagiarist. In the MLA Hand book For Writers of Research Papers,
Sr.Joseph Gibaldi has mentioned of different forms of plagiarism. According to
him, “the most blatant form of plagiarism is to obtain and submit as your own a
paper written by someone else. Other, less conspicuous form of plagiarism
includes the failure to give appropriate acknowledgement when repeating or
paraphrasing another’s wording, when taking a particular apt phrase, and when
paraphrasing another’s argument or presenting another’s line of thinking”. Thus
plagiarism is a failure to acknowledge borrowed material.
In order to avoid plagiarism we should always make a
list of all the writers and sources from which the viewpoints we have used in our
research work and should acknowledge the same. Acknowledgement may be made in
several ways-(1) in the bibliography (2) within the text, either by specific
reference or parenthetical reference or (3) in a foot note which is the
commonest form of acknowledgement.
3.8 ERRORS
TO BE AVOIDED
The most common and serious error in taking notes is
to copy the wording of the source directly, either word-for word or with minor
changes. This not only prevents the researcher in processing the information
fully into their mind, but also encourages plagiarism since the notes find
their way directly into the paper. The
best way to avoid this is not to look at your sources as you write your notes.
In that way we will be sure to use our own words. Including too many details in
notes will slow down our research work. If we are doing this, we are not
distinguishing between significant and insignificant information. Notes are
meant to be concise. Direct quotation should be used only when we have a
special purpose. If we use a direct quotation we should copy it accurately. We
should remember to include page number on notes. Otherwise, we will have to
spend valuable time, returning to the sources to find page numbers. Note taking
is thus an important phase in the process of research and it helps a lot in saving our time during the
presentation of Research paper which is dealt in the next unit.
Check Your Progress I
3.9 LET US SUM UP
In this unit we have tried to give a detail study about the note taking method
and its importance in the Research process. While taking notes for research,
many methods can be adopted by researchers according to their convenience. It
can be done either by writing down in papers or separate cards and arranging
them in an order or by using a computer. The common types of note taking method
include summarising, paraphrasing, précis and quotations which is also given
due importance in this unit. Rules to be followed while taking notes are also explained here.
As conclusion the importance in the accuracy in note taking to avoid plagiarism
is mentioned.
3.10 KEY WORDS
Paraphrase
: Expression of meaning of
passage in other words.
Précis :
Abstract or a summary.
Summary :
Abridgement or statement of chief points.
Quote :
Copy or repeat passages from.
Plagiarize :
Take and use as one’s own
UNIT 4 METHOD OF THESIS PROPOSAL AND
PRESENTATION
Contents
4.0 Objectives
4.1 Introduction
4.2 Preliminary
Section
4.3 Presenting
the Problem of the Thesis
4.4 Design
of the Study
4.5 Main
Body of the Thesis
4.6 Conclusion,
Summary and Recommendations
4.7 Reference
Material
4.8 Let
us Sum up
4.9 Key
Words
4.10 Further
Readings and References
4.0 OBJECTIVES
The main objective of this unit is to explain the
standard method of presenting a thesis or research report. In order to
communicate the result of the research work in a systematic manner its report
should well prepared. This unit provides the guidelines for it by giving in
detail the various components to be included in the report and their proper way
of arrangement. After go through this unit you will be able to:
• Understand
the fundamentals of report writing;
• Acquire
yourself with the format of a thesis;
• Identify
the various types of bibliography;
• Acquire
the skill to compile a bibliography and appendix.
4.1 INTRODUCTION
For disseminating the results of research, the
researchers have to communicate the results of their research in a systematic
manner. These written reports will be useful only if they are well prepared.
This report should be a straight forward document that clearly, precisely and
effectively describes what the researcher has done to investigate a problem.
Report writing, therefore, is an essential procedure in research. In this unit,
we are having a detail study about the method to be followed while presenting a
research report. As the research report is an exposition, it must explain the
study by giving all details of it. It must follow the rules of rhetoric , since
it is a composition and it should be well arranged. In general, a research
report consists of three parts-
• The
preliminary,
• The
text or the main body of the report,
• The
reference material.
The core forms the middle part or the main body or
text of the report. It is preceded by the preliminaries comprising the title
page, acknowledgements, table of contents etc. The core is followed by the end
part containing the appendices, bibliography etc.
4.2 PRELIMINARY SECTION
The preliminary consists of the following
components.
• The
title page
• Researcher’s
declaration
• The
certificate of the supervisor
• Preface
including acknowledgements
• Table
of contents
• List
of tables, and figures
• Abstract
or synopsis
• List
of abbreviations.
Now let us have a brief look into each of the above
items .
The title page
The first page of the report is the title page. It
should carry a concise and adequately descriptive title of the research study.
It should be precise and reflect the core of the problem under study. Even
though the format of title page differ from one to another , they usually
include- (1) the title of the study (2) the name of the degree for which it is
submitted (3) name of the author (4) the name of the institution where the
report is to be submitted and (5) the date of presentation of the report. The
entire title should be typed in all capital letters, single spaced and centred
between the right and left margins of the page. Where more than one line is
required , it should be broken and arranged to make a pleasing appearance on
the page. The statement with respect to the University ,Course and the Academic
degree for which the thesis is submitted should be typed in lower case with
capitalised initial letters below the title line. The name of the researcher
should be typed in capital letters leaving 6-2 cm from the previous statement.
The name of the institution where the report is to be submitted and the date of
of presentation of the report are typed in double space leaving 7-5 cm distance from the name of the
researcher and 2.5 cm from the bottom of the title page.
Researcher’s declaration
In case the research is undertaken by a student in
fulfilment of the requirement of a degree, he may be required to make a
declaration.
Researcher’s supervisor’s certificate
Again, in case of a student’s research work , his
research supervisor has to certify that it was a record of independent research
work done by the student.
Preface including
acknowledgements
A preface may include reasons, why, in the first
place, the topic was selected by the researcher. The relevance of a study may
also be mentioned here. If the researcher has opted to discuss the significance
and nature of his research in ‘introductory chapter’ then he may not write
preface. But he can use the page to make acknowledgements. Here the researcher
acknowledges the assistance and support received from individuals and
organisations in conducting the research. Here thank all those who have helped
him for a variety of reasons including guidance, during the period of study. It
is thus intended to show his gratitude. The comments , given in
acknowledgements should be brief, simple , temperate and modest and given only
for substantial assistance and cooperation of a non- routine character which
warrants public recognition.
Table of contents
The table of contents appear after the preface and
it gives an outline of the contents of the thesis. It contains a list of the
chapters and their sub-titles with page numbers. Subtitles, however, should be
indented under each chapter title and be followed by the specific page or
section references. If reference to specific pages for subtitles is not
desired, the subtitles may run together
and separated by semi- colons or dashes. When so many subheadings exist it may
give an overcrowded look if all these are included in the table of contents.
Hence, these may be placed at the beginning of that particular chapter below
the title. It thus facilitates ready location of topics in the report.
The table of content also include the preface/
acknowledgement, list of tables and figures etc. The heading “Table of
Contents” should be the centre at the top of the page and in capital letters.
The chapter headings may be typed in capital letters and subtitles in small
letters. Small letters should be used for the subheadings except for the
initial letter and of all nouns, pronouns , verbs etc. On the right hand side
should be typed the heading “Page” at the right margin below which page numbers
will appear. On the left hand side will appear the headings in the sequence in
which they actually appear in the thesis.
List of Tables and figures
If table and figures are included in the report,
separate pages for them should follow the table of contents. Figures refer to
map, drawings, graphs, charts, diagrams etc. The full titles of tables and
figures, worded exactly as they appear in text, arte presented with
corresponding /consecutive numbers and page locations. Arabic numerals are
usually used for identifying tables, figures etc. In the list of table and
figures, the titles should be typed with initial capitals , rather than all
capital letters.
Abstract or
synopsis
An abstract is a summary of the findings of the
research work. It should be as brief as possible and run about only one or two pages. It is
placed at the prefatory part of the report so that a reader can get a quick
overview of the report. Along with the summary of the findings or result of the
investigation, it states in brief the purpose and scope of the study and also
the method used for the research work. Here care should be taken that there is
no over emphasis of the minor points and also that important points has to be
treated adequately.
Abbreviations
Only
such names are to be abbreviated which are likely to appear too often in the
report. Name of persons are never abbreviated. Most of the forms of
abbreviations are universally accepted because of the international readership
of the scholarly dissertations and thesis. The list of abbreviations should
appear before the beginning of the main text.
4.3 PRESENTING THE PROBLEM OF THE THESIS
After the prefatory items, the body of the report is
presented. It is the major part of the report. In a comprehensive report, the
body of the report will consist of several chapters. The division of the report
into chapter or sections should reflect the organisation of the parts with one
another and with the whole; i.e.; the division should be logical to make the
contents meaningful. The text usually consists of- (1) Introduction (2) Design
of the study (3) Main body of the report
(4) Summary, conclusions and recommendations.
Introduction
This is the first chapter in the body of a research
report. It is devoted for introducing the theoretical background of the
portion, its definition and formulation. It should be presented in such a way
that it interests the reader in the subject matter of research. It must not be
dull and lack in precession. It may consist of the following sections.
Theoretical
background of the topic
Here the researcher introduces the background and
the nature of the problem so as to place it into a larger context to enable the
reader to know its significance in a proper perspective. This section
summarises the theory or a conceptual frame work within which the problem has
been investigated.
Statement of the
problem
In this section the researcher has to point out why
and how the problem under research was selected. There is a need of clear
statement of the nature of the problem with specific questions to be answered
or hypothesis to be tested. A consideration of significance of the problem and
its historical background is also a need. Hence in this section the problem is
clearly defined and its facets and significance are pointed out. For this the
problem may be broken down into constituent elements or major subdivisions.
Review literature
This is an important part of the introductory
chapter. Here a brief review of previous studies on the problem and significant
writings on the topic under study is stated. Thus it is summarising the current
status of research work already done in the research area sought. Previous
research studies are abstracted and significant writings of authorities in the
area under study are review. Such a review provides a background for the
development of the present study and makes the reader up to date. Brief summary
indicating areas of agreement or disagreement in findings or gaps in existing
knowledge should be included. How the research work is an attempt to fill that
gap is highlighted in this part of the introduction.
Significance of the study
The significance of the problem, the contribution
that the study is expected to make, its practical importance and the national
relevance is specifically indicated in this section.
The scope of the
study
The dimensions of the study in terms of the geographical
area covered, the designation of the population being studied or the exact
coverage of the study is mentioned here.
The objectives of
the study
The objectives of the study and investigative
questions relating to each of the objectives are presented.
Hypotheses
The specific hypotheses to be tested are stated. The
sources of their formulation may be indicated.
Definition of
concepts
The operational definitions of the key concepts of
the study are presented here. i.e., various concepts or domains proposed to be
used in a research requires to be stated. Definitions or special meanings of
all important terms so as to enable the reader to understand the concepts
underlying the investigation is to be indicated. How those concepts are defined
by early writers and how the definition of the researcher were an improvement
over earlier definition may be explained.
4.4 DESIGN OF THE STUDY
This part of the thesis is devoted for the
presentation of all the aspects of the methodology and their implementation
,i.e., methods of data collection instruments, methods of data processing and
plan of analysis. Most of this material is taken from the research proposal
plan. The revisions, if any made therefore should be clearly stated. The
details of the study’s design should be fully stated so as to enable another
researcher to reproduce the study and test its conclusions.
Methodology
In this
section, the overall typology of research used and the data collection methods
employed are described. It also describes how the field work was carried out,
the reliability of instruments selected and the statistical tools and
procedures used in the analysis.
1. Sources of data:- The sources from which the
primary and secondary data were gathered are stated. The limitations of secondary
data also should be indicated.
2. Sampling plan:- The size of the universe from
which the sample was drawn, the sampling methods adopted and the sample size
and process of sampling are described in this section. The estimate of sampling
error and what were originally planned and what were achieved are also to be
given. These details are essential for determining the limitations of the
funding.
3. Data collection instruments:- The types of
instruments used for data collection and their contents, scales and other
devices used for measuring variables and the procedure of establishing their
validity and reliability are described in this section.
4. Field work:- When and how the field work was
conducted and what problems and difficulties were faced during the field work
are described under this sub-heading. The description of field experience will
provide valuable lessons for future researchers in organising and conducting
their field work.
5. Data processing and analysis plan:- The method
adopted for data processing and an account of methods used for data analysis
and testing hypothesis must be out lined and justified. If common methods are
used there is only a need to mention about them. But of an unusual method was
used, sufficient details of them has to e described so as to enable the reader
to understand it.
Chapterisation:- Chapterisation or the scheme of
chapters in the main body of the thesis and their interrelationship is briefly
described in this section in order to give an overview of the presentation of
the results of the study.
Limits of the study:- All research designs have
limitations and so do all research implementations .Such limitations may
vitiate the conclusions and their generalisations. The sincere investigator
faces these problems and he reports them carefully and honestly in the
introduction itself. This will help the reader to judge the validity of the
conclusions and the general worth of the study in the proper perspective.
4.5 MAIN BODY OF THE THESIS
This is the heart of the research report and
probably the largest section of the report. It should be an organised
presentation of the results and each major division of the problem should be
presented in a separate chapter. The chapters should be well- balanced,
mutually related and arranged in logical sequence. Each chapter should be given
an appropriate heading. The chapter should include a discussion of the issue or
part of the problem investigated and evidence used in its solution. If this
becomes lengthy a summary of the evidence may be made at the end of the
chapter. Through textual situation and tabular and graphic devices, the data
are critically analysed and interpreted. Every table or chart should be
self-contained and self-explanatory unit within the body of the report, and the
presentation should be so clear that the reader be able to grasp the finding
either by reading the text or looking at the table or chart.
The results should be reported as accurately and
completely as possible. The data themselves should be described fully, they
should be analysed in detail and all the evidence resulting from the analysis
should be presented. These chapters are primarily for the use of the reader who
wishes to make a detailed study of the problem. So every bit of relevant
evidence should be supported by logical reasoning and empirical facts.
Materials should be organised systematically and presented under appropriate
headings and subheadings. Each chapter should end with a summary and lead into
the next section or chapter with a smooth transition sentence.
4.6 CONCLUSION, SUMMARY AND RECOMMENDATIONS
This is the last part of the text of the thesis.
This chapter is more extensive than the abstract given in the beginning of the
report. This chapter should be a self contained summary of the whole report,
containing a summary of essential background, information, findings and
conclusions and recommendations. It consists of the summary, conclusions or
generalisation, suggestions and recommendations. The summary may be more or
less a restatement of the topical sentences of the various findings. Summaries
of findings may be subordinated under the conclusion statements. All these
statements may be numbered or coded in some way so that they refer to pages or
tables in the findings sections, upon which they are based. After a brief
statement of the problem, the purpose of the study and the methodology used in
the investigation, the findings and conclusions are presented. Findings are
statements of factual information based upon the data analysis. Conclusions are
inferences or generalisations drawn from the findings and relate to hypotheses.
They are answers to the questions of the hypothesis proposed . The formulation
of conclusion is the most difficult aspect of report writings. A research may
sometimes be tempted to over generalise . Hence it is necessary to be modest.
Besides summary and conclusion, recommendations are
also required from the investigator . Recommendations are typically brief
statements of a limited number of suggestions for further consideration. These
should flow from the findings and conclusions. They should be specific and
should not be mere vague statements. Suggestions must be practicable and based
on logical reasoning and are to be given at the end of the report. The research
report should aim to give leads to future research scholars. The researcher
should be able to give directions to the future researchers from the insights
he has gained during the investigations. Hence, it may be appropriate in concluding
this part of the report to indicate topics which need further research, i.e.,
the reporter should explain in the beginning the relationship of his research
to previous work on the subject (review literature) and at last suggest what
part of the field would more benefit, perhaps on a bigger scale or from a
different angle.
4.7 REFERENCE MATERIAL
The core part of the thesis is followed by the end
part containing the appendices and the bibliography. Thus the end part of the
report is made up of : Bibliography (2) Appendices (3) Index
Bibliography
A bibliography means a list of written sources
consulted in preparation of the report during the course of research. It lists
all published and unpublished references used by the writer in preparing the
report. It may refer to all documents like books, periodicals , articles,
government documents, pamphlets, lectures, interviews etc, which have bearing
on the thesis irrespective of their being actually referred to or not, in the
text. The aim is to permit the reader to find the exact items the writer
consulted. There are different kinds of bibliography like, References or
literature cited comprises a list of documents which is confined only to those
works actually cited in text or the footnotes of the report. Sources consulted
consist of a comprehensive listing of books and papers consulted including
those which are not strictly relevant to the subject of the thesis. Selected
bibliography contains those sources cited, together with the more relevant of
the works which have been consulted. Bibliographical notes is a brief annoted
bibliography where the references are combined with the bibliography list.
Bibliography may be arranged according to the
alphabetical order, chronological order, divisions of the subject etc.
Generally the simplest and best arrangement for a short bibliography is the
alphabetical order. Here the last name of the author (surname) is listed first,
separated from the full name and arrange it alphabetically by surname. Some
list of books is most convenient if arranged in the chronological order of the
publication. This is suited for works in history. Writers sometimes desire to
make separate divisions for primary and secondary sources. But usual practice
favours one comprehensive listing of both the sources together. Alternatively,
the bibliography may be classified into three or four sections- (1) Books (2)
Articles (3) Reports and (4) Other documents and in each section relevant
references may be arranged in alphabetical order. The purpose of bibliography
is different from that of footnotes. While bibliography is a list of all
materials related to the topic of research, the footnotes specifically
paraphrased materials are found. Care should be taken by the researcher while
bibliography listing and it should be done in the proper format.
Appendix
An appendix is used for additional materials which
has not found place in the main text. It includes (a) copies if data collection
instruments like questionnaire used for the study or interview schedules,(b)
technical details on sampling plan (c) complex and long primary tables (d)
statistical computation (e) supporting documents or any other material evidence
of considerable reference value. By relegating such supporting evidence to an
appendix, the text of the report remains uncluttered yet the argument is not
weakened because the interested reader can be directed to consult particular
pages of an appendix for further detail. Thus those materials given in
appendices are not directly essential for a understanding of the text, but
useful as a supporting evidence. Appendices may be placed between the final
chapter and the bibliography or immediately after the bibliography. All
appendices should be separated and listed accordingly in the Table of contents
together with page numbers. Here pages are numbered usually having Arabic
numerals. Each appendix should be referred to in the body of the thesis.
Index
The index, if prepared should give an alphabetically
arranged references to all important matters discussed in the report. It may be
either subject index or another index. To conclude, we can say that a thesis or
a research report is an authoritative document based on research work. It
presents highly specific information. The written reports will be useful only
when they are well prepared and while preparing the report due attention has to
be paid to represent the above mentioned components. Then only the report will
be properly organised and can be communicated to others.
Check Your Progress I
4.8 LET US SUM UP
This unit deals with the prescriptions of contents
and form of reporting suitable for communicating the results of the research to
others. Mainly, the research report is divided into three parts, i.e.,
preliminary, main body of the report and the reference materials. All these
three sections consist of different components which are studied in detail in
this unit. Many of the components among this are familiar to all. But some
others are not so. This unit explain the standard way of presenting such components
also along with the familiar elements. This helps us to follow established
standards while reporting and this make the thesis comprehensive and accurate.
4.9 KEY WORDS
Rhetoric
: Art of writing.
Variable
: A quality which changes.
Exposition
: Explanation of a theory.
Hypothesis
: Suggested explanation of
something.
Index : Alphabetical list of inferences.
Preface
: Introduction to book.
Great article.I am so happy with your blog.
ReplyDeleteUK dissertation
thanks for your encouragement.....
Delete